* A Distributed Proofreaders Canada eBook *

This eBook is made available at no cost and with very few restrictions. These restrictions apply only if (1) you make a change in the eBook (other than alteration for different display devices), or (2) you are making commercial use of the eBook. If either of these conditions applies, please check with an FP administrator before proceeding.

This work is in the Canadian public domain, but may be under copyright in some countries. If you live outside Canada, check your country's copyright laws. If the book is under copyright in your country, do not download or redistribute this file.

Title: Studies in Words

Date of first publication: 1960

Author: Clive Staples Lewis (1898-1963)

Date first posted: June 26, 2018

Date last updated: June 26, 2018

Faded Page eBook #20180648

This eBook was produced by: Delphine Lettau, Stephen Hutcheson & the online Distributed Proofreaders Canada team at http://www.pgdpcanada.net





Studies in Words

STUDIES IN WORDS

BY
C. S. LEWIS
Professor of Medieval and Renaissance English in the University of Cambridge and Fellow of Magdalene College

CAMBRIDGE
AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS
1960

TO
STANLEY AND
JOAN BENNETT

iv

PUBLISHED BY
THE SYNDICS OF THE CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Bentley House, 200 Euston Road, London, N.W.1
American Branch: 32 East 57th Street, New York 22, N.Y.
©
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
1960

First printed 1960
Reprinted 1960

Printed in Great Britain at the University Press, Cambridge
(Brooke Crutchley, University Printer)

v

CONTENTS

  Preface page vii
1 INTRODUCTION 1
2 NATURE (with Phusis, Kind, Physical etc.) 24
3 SAD (with Gravis) 75
4 WIT (with Ingenium) 86
5 FREE (with Eleutherios, Liberal, Frank etc.) 111
6 SENSE (with Sentence, Sensibility and Sensible) 133
7 SIMPLE 165
8 CONSCIENCE AND CONSCIOUS 181
9 AT THE FRINGE OF LANGUAGE 214
  Index 233
vii

PREFACE

This book is based on lectures given at Cambridge during the last few years and is primarily addressed to students. I have indeed hoped that others also might find it of interest but I must warn them what it is not. It is not an essay in the higher linguistics. The ultimate nature of language and the theory of meaning are not here my concern. The point of view is merely lexical and historical. My words are studied as an aid to more accurate reading and chosen for the light they throw on ideas and sentiments. The notes on some common types of semantic change given in the first chapter are a rough and ready attempt at practical guidance; if any deeper issues are raised by implication, this was not my intention. C. S. L.

CAMBRIDGE

June 1959

1

1
INTRODUCTION

This book has grown out of a practice which was at first my necessity and later my hobby; whether at last it has attained the dignity of a study, others must decide. In my young days when I had to take my pupils through Anglo-Saxon and Middle English texts neither they nor I could long be content to translate a word in the sense which its particular context demanded while leaving the different senses it bore in other places to be memorised, without explanation, as if they were wholly different words. Natural curiosity and mnemonic thrift drove us, as it drives others, to link them up and to see, where possible, how they could have radiated out from a central meaning. Once embarked, it was impossible not to be curious about the later senses of those which survived into Modern English. Margins and notebooks thus became steadily fuller. One saw increasingly that sixteenth- and even nineteenth-century texts needed such elucidation not very much more rarely, and in a more subtle way, than those of the eleventh or twelfth; for in the older books one knows what one does not understand but in the later one discovers, often after years of contented misreading, that one has been interpolating senses later than those the author intended. And all the while one seems to be learning not only about words. In the end the habit becomes second nature; the slightest semantic discomfort 2 in one’s reading rouses one, like a terrier, to the game. No doubt I thus learned rather laboriously from my own reading some things that could have been learned more quickly from the N.E.D. But I would advise everyone to do the same so far—a serious qualification—as his time allows. One understands a word much better if one has met it alive, in its native habitat. So far as is possible our knowledge should be checked and supplemented, not derived, from the dictionary.

At the same time a prospective reader may reasonably ask what difference there will be, for him, between reading one of my chapters and looking up one of my words in the dictionary. The answer is that I offer both less and more. Less, because I do not even attempt to be exhaustive; as regards the greater words I am already too old to hope for that. I offer more, first, because I drive words of different languages abreast. I depart from classical English philology by having no concern with sounds, nor with derivations simply as such. I am concerned solely with the semantic relations of, say, natura and nature; the fact that one is ‘derived’ from the other is for my purpose unimportant. That is why phusis and kind come in with just as good a title as natura. Something will be said later about what I think can be gained from such a procedure. And secondly, I have been able to say more about the history of thought and sentiment which underlies the semantic biography of a word than would have been possible or proper in a dictionary. I have of course checked my results by the N.E.D. It has often given me the perfect example for which I had searched my own 3 reading in vain; often (pereant qui ante nos!) mortified me by anticipating the beautiful example I had already found for myself; and sometimes given what I thought, perhaps with foolish partiality, to be not so good an example as mine. In a few places, not without diffidence, I have ventured to dissent from it.

The readers I have principally in view are students. One of my aims is to facilitate, as regards certain words, a more accurate reading of old books; and therefore to encourage everyone to similar exploration of many other words. I am sometimes told that there are people who want a study of literature wholly free from philology; that is, from the love and knowledge of words. Perhaps no such people exist. If they do, they are either crying for the moon or else resolving on a lifetime of persistent and carefully guarded delusion. If we read an old poem with insufficient regard for change in the overtones, and even the dictionary meanings, of words since its date—if, in fact, we are content with whatever effect the words accidentally produce in our modern minds—then of course we do not read the poem the old writer intended. What we get may still be, in our opinion, a poem; but it will be our poem, not his. If we call this tout court ‘reading’ the old poet, we are deceiving ourselves. If we reject as ‘mere philology’ every attempt to restore for us his real poem, we are safeguarding the deceit. Of course any man is entitled to say he prefers the poems he makes for himself out of his mistranslations to the poems the writers intended. I have no quarrel with him. He need have none with me. Each to his taste.

4

And to avoid this, knowledge is necessary. Intelligence and sensibility by themselves are not enough. This is well illustrated by an example within my own experience. In the days of the old School Certificate we once set as a gobbet from Julius Caesar

Is Brutus sick and is it physical

To walk unbraced and suck up the humours

Of the dank morning[1]

and one boy explained physical as ‘sensible, sane; the opposite of “mental” or mad’. It would be crass to laugh at that boy’s ignorance without also admiring his extreme cleverness. The ignorance is laughable because it could have been avoided. But if that ignorance had been inevitable—as similar ignorances often are when we are dealing with an ancient book—if so much linguistic history were lost that we did not and could not know the sense ‘mad’ for mental and the antithesis of mental-physical to be far later than Shakespeare’s time, then his suggestion would deserve to be hailed as highly intelligent. We should indeed probably accept it, at least provisionally, as correct. For it makes excellent sense of the passage and also accounts for the meaning it gives to physical by a semantic process which—if we did not know that chronology ruled it out—we should regard as very possible.

So far from being secured against such errors, the highly intelligent and sensitive reader will, without knowledge, be most in danger of them. His mind bubbles over with 5 possible meanings. He has ready to hand un-thought-of metaphors, highly individual shades of feeling, subtle associations, ambiguities—every manner of semantic gymnastics—which he can attribute to his author. Hence the difficulty of ‘making sense’ out of a strange phrase will seldom be for him insuperable. Where the duller reader simply does not understand, he misunderstands—triumphantly, brilliantly. But it is not enough to make sense. We want to find the sense the author intended. ‘Brilliant’ explanations of a passage often show that a clever, insufficiently informed man has found one more mare’s nest. The wise reader, far from boasting an ingenuity which will find sense in what looks like nonsense, will not accept even the most slightly strained meaning until he is quite sure that the history of the word does not permit something far simpler. The smallest semantic discomfort rouses his suspicions. He notes the key word and watches for its recurrence in other texts. Often they will explain the whole puzzle.

By driving words from different languages abreast I have been able to bring out something which interests me far more than derivations. We find in the history, say, of phusis, natura, and kind, or again in that of eleutherios, liberalis, free, and frank, similar or even identical semantic operations being performed quite independently. The speakers who achieved them belonged to different stocks and lived in different countries at different periods, and they started with different linguistic tools. In an age when the linguistic analysts have made us afraid that our thought may be almost wholly conditioned by our speech this 6 seems to me encouraging. Apparently there is at least some independence. There is something, either in the structure of the mind or in the things it thinks about, which can produce the same results under very different conditions.

After hearing one chapter of this book when it was still a lecture, a man remarked to me ‘You have made me afraid to say anything at all’. I know what he meant. Prolonged thought about the words which we ordinarily use to think with can produce a momentary aphasia. I think it is to be welcomed. It is well we should become aware of what we are doing when we speak, of the ancient, fragile, and (well used) immensely potent instruments that words are.

This implies that I have an idea of what is good and bad language. I have. Language is an instrument for communication. The language which can with the greatest ease make the finest and most numerous distinctions of meaning is the best. It is better to have like and love than to have aimer for both. It was better to have the older English distinction between ‘I haven’t got indigestion’ (I am not suffering from it at the moment) and ‘I don’t have indigestion’ (I am not a dyspeptic) than to level both, as America has now taught most Englishmen to do, under ‘I don’t have’.

In the following pages we shall see good words, or good senses of words, losing their edge or, more rarely, recovering it or getting a new edge that serves some different purpose. I have tried not to obtrude the moral, but I should be glad if I sent any reader away with a new 7 sense of responsibility to the language. It is unnecessary defeatism to believe that we can do nothing about it. Our conversation will have little effect; but if we get into print—perhaps especially if we are leader-writers, reviewers, or reporters—we can help to strengthen or weaken some disastrous vogue word; can encourage a good, and resist a bad, gallicism or Americanism. For many things the press prints today will be taken up by the great mass of speakers in a few years.

Verbicide, the murder of a word, happens in many ways. Inflation is one of the commonest; those who taught us to say awfully for ‘very’, tremendous for ‘great’, sadism for ‘cruelty’, and unthinkable for ‘undesirable’ were verbicides. Another way is verbiage, by which I here mean the use of a word as a promise to pay which is never going to be kept. The use of significant as if it were an absolute, and with no intention of ever telling us what the thing is significant of, is an example. So is diametrically when it is used merely to put opposite into the superlative. Men often commit verbicide because they want to snatch a word as a party banner, to appropriate its ‘selling quality’. Verbicide was committed when we exchanged Whig and Tory for Liberal and Conservative. But the greatest cause of verbicide is the fact that most people are obviously far more anxious to express their approval and disapproval of things than to describe them. Hence the tendency of words to become less descriptive and more evaluative; then to become evaluative, while still retaining some hint of the sort of goodness or badness implied; and to end up by being purely evaluative—useless 8 synonyms for good or for bad. We shall see this happening to the word villain in a later chapter. Rotten, paradoxically has become so completely a synonym for ‘bad’ that we now have to say bad when we mean ‘rotten’.

I am not suggesting that we can by an archaising purism repair any of the losses that have already occurred. It may not, however, be entirely useless to resolve that we ourselves will never commit verbicide. If modern critical usage seems to be initiating a process which might finally make adolescent and contemporary mere synonyms for bad and good—and stranger things have happened—we should banish them from our vocabulary. I am tempted to adapt the couplet we see in some parks—

Let no one say, and say it to your shame,

That there was meaning here before you came.

I will close this chapter with a ‘statement’, as the musicians say, of certain themes which will recur in those that follow.

I. THE EFFECTS OF RAMIFICATION

As everyone knows, words constantly take on new meanings. Since these do not necessarily, nor even usually, obliterate the old ones, we should picture this process not on the analogy of an insect undergoing metamorphoses but rather on that of a tree throwing out new branches, which themselves throw out subordinate branches; in fact, as ramification. The new branches sometimes overshadow and kill the old ones but by no means always. We shall again and again find the earliest senses 9 of a word flourishing for centuries despite a vast overgrowth of later senses which might have been expected to kill them.

The philologist’s dream is to diagrammatise all the meanings of a word so as to have a perfect semantic tree of it; every twig traced to its branch, every branch traced back to the trunk. That this can seldom, if ever, be perfectly achieved does not matter much; all studies end in doubts. But there is apparently some real danger of forgetting that the overwhelming majority of those who use the word neither know nor care anything about the tree. And even those who do know something of it most often use the word without thinking about it. Just in the same way, all men use their muscles when they move but most men do not know or care what muscles they are using; and even anatomists, who do know, are not usually thinking of this during a game of tennis. When we use one word in many different senses we avail ourselves of the results produced by semantic ramification. We can do this successfully without being aware of them.

That is why I cannot agree with Professor Empson’s suggestion[2] that when we say ‘Use your sense, man!’ we are implying that the intellectual effort demanded is as easy as the reception of a sense-impression—in other words that we are using sense (i.e. sense-perception) metaphorically. Particular objections will be found in a later chapter: the ramification which produced for the word sense the two meanings (gumption and sense-perception) is well over two thousand years old, and need not have 10 had anything to do with metaphor. It is handed to the modern speaker ‘on a plate’. And that is the general principle I am here concerned with. If we neglect the semantic history of a word we shall be in danger of attributing to ordinary speakers an individual semantic agility which in reality they neither have nor need. It is perfectly true that we hear very simple people daily using several different senses of one word with perfect accuracy—like a dancer in a complicated dance. But this is not because they understand either the relation between them or their history.

Each new speaker learns his native language chiefly by imitation, partly by those hurried scraps of amateur lexicography which his elders produce in answer to the frequent question ‘What does that mean?’ He does not at first—how should he?—distinguish between different senses of one word and different words. They all have to be learned in the same way. Memory and the faculty of imitation, not semantic gymnastics, enable him to speak about sentences in a Latin exercise and sentences of imprisonment, about a cardboard box and a box at the theatre. He does not even ask which are different words and which merely different senses. Nor, for the most part, do we. How many adults know whether bows of ships and bows taught by the dancing master—or down (a hill) and down (deorsum)—or a boys’ school and a school of porpoises—are accidental homophones (like neat and neat or arms and arms) or products of ramification?

A child may, of course, be philologically minded. If so, it may construct imaginary semantic trees for itself. But 11 it does so to explain the usages it has already learned; the usage is not a result of the theory. As a child I—probably like many others—evolved the theory that a candlestick was so called ‘because it makes the candle stick up’. But that wasn’t why I called it a candlestick. I called it a candlestick because everyone else did.

II. THE INSULATING POWER OF THE CONTEXT

It is this most important principle that enables speakers to give half a dozen different meanings to a single word with very little danger of confusion. If ambiguity (in Professor Empson’s sense) were not balanced by this power, communication would become almost impossible. There is, I understand, a species of modern poetry which is so written that it cannot be fully received unless all the possible senses of words are operative in the reader’s mind. Whether there was any such poetry before the present century—whether all old poetry thus read is misread—are questions we need not discuss here. What seems to me certain is that in ordinary language the sense of a word is governed by the context and this sense normally excludes all others from the mind. When we see the notice ‘Wines and Spirits’ we do not think about angels, devils, ghosts and fairies—nor about the ‘spirits’ of the older medical theory. When someone speaks about the Stations of the Cross we do not think about railway stations nor about our station in life.

The proof of this is that the sudden intrusion of any irrelevant sense—in other words the voluntary or involuntary pun—is funny. It is funny because it is unexpected. 12 There is a semantic explosion because the two meanings rush together from a great distance; one of them was not in our consciousness at all till that moment. If it had been, there would be no detonation. This comes out very clearly in those numerous stories which decorum forbids me to recall (in print); stories where some august person such as a headmistress or a bishop, on a platform, gravely uses a word in one sense, blissfully forgetful of some other and very unsuitable sense—producing a ludicrous indecency. It will usually be found that the audience, like the speaker, had till then quite forgotten it too. For the shouts of open, or the sibilations of suppressed, laughter do not usually begin at once but after several seconds. The obscene intruder, the uninvited semantic guest, has taken that time to come up from the depths where he lay asleep, off duty.

It is of course the insulating power of the context which enables old senses to persist, uncontaminated by newer ones. Thus train (of a dress) and train (on the railway), or civil (courteous) and civil (not military), or magazine (a store) and magazine (a periodical), do not interfere with one another because they are unlikely to occur in the same context. They live happily by keeping out of each other’s way.

III. THE DANGEROUS SENSE

When a word has several meanings historical circumstances often make one of them dominant during a particular period. Thus station is now more likely to mean a railway-station than anything else; evolution, more likely 13 to bear its biological sense than any other. When I was a boy estate had as its dominant meaning ‘land belonging to a large landowner’, but the meaning ‘land covered with small houses’ is dominant now.

The dominant sense of any word lies uppermost in our minds. Wherever we meet the word, our natural impulse will be to give it that sense. When this operation results in nonsense, of course, we see our mistake and try over again. But if it makes tolerable sense our tendency is to go merrily on. We are often deceived. In an old author the word may mean something different. I call such senses dangerous senses because they lure us into misreadings. In examining a word I shall often have to distinguish one of its meanings as its dangerous sense, and I shall symbolise this by writing the word (in italics) with the letters d.s. after it.

Thus, since ‘safety’ is the dangerous sense of the word security the symbol security (d.s.) would stand for ‘security in the sense of safety’. Similarly philosophy (d.s.) means ‘philosophy in the sense of metaphysics, epistemology, logic, etc. as distinct from the natural sciences’—the sense we are in danger of reading into it when old writers actually mean by it just science. Fellow (d.s.) would be ‘fellow used as a contemptuous vocative’.

When the dangerous sense is a sense which did not exist at all in the age when our author wrote, it is less dangerous. Moderate, and moderately increasing, scholarship will guard us against it. But often the situation is more delicate. What is now the dangerous sense may have existed then but it may not yet have been at all dominant. 14 It may possibly be the sense the old author really intended, but this is not nearly so probable as our own usage leads us to suppose. Our task is not the comparatively simple one of excluding an unqualified candidate; we have to conquer our undue predilection for one of those who are qualified.

IV. THE WORD’S MEANING AND THE SPEAKER’S MEANING

I use speaker throughout to cover writer as well.

The distinction between what a word means and what a speaker means by a word appears in its crudest form, of course, when a foreigner or imperfectly educated native is actually mistaken as to standard usage and commits a malapropism; using deprecate, say, to mean ‘depreciate’, or disinterested to mean ‘bored’, or scarify to mean ‘scare’. But this is not what I have in mind. Speaker’s meaning and word’s meaning may be distinguishable where there is no lexical mistake involved.

‘When I spoke of supper after the theatre, I meant by supper a biscuit and a cup of cocoa. But my friend meant by supper something like a cold bird and a bottle of wine.’ In this situation both parties might well have agreed on the lexical (or ‘dictionary’) meaning of supper; perhaps ‘a supernumerary meal which, if taken at all, is the last meal before bed’. In another way they ‘meant’ different things by it. The use of the verb mean both for the word’s force and for the speaker’s intention can doubtless be criticised, and distinctions could be drawn. But I am not here embarking on ‘the meaning of meaning’ nor high linguistics. That will not be necessary. To use mean thus 15 without further distinction is good English and will serve our turn.

For there is only one reason why the difference between the speaker’s and the word’s meaning concerns us. It is this. If some speaker’s meaning becomes very common it will in the end establish itself as one of the word’s meanings; this is one of the ways in which semantic ramification comes about.

For thousands of Englishmen today the word furniture has only one sense—a (not very easily definable) class of domestic movables. And doubtless many people, if they should read Berkeley’s ‘all the choir of heaven and furniture of earth’, would take this use of furniture to be a metaphorical application of the sense they know—that which is to earth as tables and chairs and so forth are to a house. Even those who know the larger meaning of the word (whatever ‘furnishes’ in the sense of stocking, equipping, or replenishing) would certainly admit ‘domestic movables’ as one of its senses. It would in fact, by my system, be furniture (d.s.). But it must have become one of the word’s meanings by being a very common speaker’s meaning. Men who said ‘my furniture’ were often in fact, within that context, referring to their domestic movables. The word did not yet mean that; they meant it. When I say ‘Take away this rubbish’ I usually ‘mean’ these piles of old newspapers, magazines, and Christmas cards. That is not what the word rubbish means. But if a sufficiently large number of people shared my distaste for that sort of litter, and applied the word rubbish to it often enough, the word might come to have 16 this as one of its senses. So with furniture, which, from being a speaker’s meaning, has established itself so firmly as one of the word’s meanings that it has ousted all the others in popular speech.

Estate is acquiring the dominant sense ‘building estate’ in our own time by just the same process. Morality and immorality have in the same way come to mean ‘chastity’ and ‘lechery’. These are the forms of virtue and vice which both the prudish and the prurient most want to talk about. And since most of us have a dash of prudery or prurience and many among us of both, we may say simply ‘which most people most want to talk about’. The speaker’s meaning of ‘all that immorality’ was so often ‘all that lechery’ that lechery becomes one of the word’s meanings; indeed, outside highly educated circles, its only meaning.

This is one of the most troublesome phenomena for the historian of a word. If you want to know when ‘domestic movables’ became one of the meanings (word’s meanings) of furniture, it is no good just finding the earliest example where the things referred to as furniture in that context obviously were in fact domestic movables. The usage might record merely a speaker’s meaning. You cannot infer a ‘word’s meaning’ any more than you can infer from my most habitual use of rubbish that rubbish (lexically) had ‘old newspapers etc.’ as one of its senses in 1958. An old writer may use the word gentle of conduct which was clearly in fact what we call gentle (mild, soft, not severe); or may use wit to describe what was clearly in fact wit (d.s.); or cattle referring to what we call ‘cattle’. But none 17 of these prove the existence of the modern word’s meaning at that date. They might all be speaker’s meanings.

V. TACTICAL DEFINITIONS

Most of us who are interested in such things soon learn that if you want to discover how a man pronounces a word it is no use asking him. Many people will produce in reply the pronunciation which their snobbery or anti-snobbery makes them think the most desirable. Honest and self-critical people will often be reduced to saying, ‘Well, now you ask me, I don’t really know’. Anyway, with the best will in the world, it is extraordinarily difficult to sound a word—thus produced cold and without context for inspection—exactly as one would sound it in real conversation. The proper method is quite different. You must stealthily guide the talk into subjects which will force him to use the word you are chasing. You will then hear his real pronunciation; the one he uses when he is off his guard, the one he doesn’t know he uses.

It is with meanings something the same. In determining what a word meant at any period in the past we may get some help from the dictionaries of that period; especially from bi-lingual dictionaries. These are the most trustworthy because their purpose was usually humble and practical; the writer really wants to give you the nearest English equivalent of the Latin or Italian word. A purely English dictionary is more likely to be influenced by the lexicographer’s ideas of how words ought to be used; therefore worse evidence of how they actually were used.

18

But when we leave the dictionaries we must view all definitions with grave distrust. It is the greatest simplicity in the world to suppose that when, say, Dryden defines wit or Arnold defines poetry, we can use their definition as evidence of what the word really meant when they wrote. The fact that they define it at all is itself a ground for scepticism. Unless we are writing a dictionary, or a text-book of some technical subject, we define our words only because we are in some measure departing from their real current sense. Otherwise there would be no purpose in doing so. This is especially true of negative definitions. Statements that honour, or freedom, or humour, or wealth, ‘does not mean’ this or that are proof that it was beginning to mean, or even had long meant, precisely this or that. We tell our pupils that deprecate does not mean depreciate or that immorality does not mean simply lechery because these words are beginning to mean just those things. We are in fact resisting the growth of a new sense. We may be quite right to do so, for it may be one that will make English a less useful means of communication. But we should not be resisting it unless it had already appeared. We do not warn our pupils that coalbox does not mean a hippopotamus.

The chapter devoted to the word wit will illustrate this. We shall find old critics giving definitions of it which are contradicted not only by other evidence but out of the critics’ own mouths. Off their guard they can be caught using it in the very sense their definition was contrived to exclude. A student who should read the critical debate of the seventeenth century on wit under the impression that 19 what the critics say they mean by wit is always, or often, what they really mean by wit would end in total bewilderment. He must understand that such definitions are purely tactical. They are attempts to appropriate for one side, and to deny to the other, a potent word. You can see the same ‘war of positions’ going on today. A certain type of writer begins ‘The essence of poetry is’ or ‘All vulgarity may be defined as’, and then produces a definition which no one ever thought of since the world began, which conforms to no one’s actual usage, and which he himself will probably have forgotten by the end of the month. The phenomenon ceases to be puzzling only when we realise that it is a tactical definition. The pretty word has to be narrowed ad hoc so as to exclude something he dislikes. The ugly word has to be extended ad hoc, or more probably ad hunc, so as to bespatter some enemy. Nineteenth-century definitions of the word gentleman are also tactical.

I do not of course say (for I don’t know) that such definitions cannot have uses of their own. But that of giving information about the actual meaning of a word is not one of them.

VI. THE METHODOLOGICAL IDIOM

Suppose that a conversation which we overhear contains the remark ‘I’m afraid Jones’s psychology will be his undoing’. Most of us, I suppose, would take this to mean that the state of his psyche will endanger his success and happiness. But suppose we then discover that the conversation is between two examiners; that Jones is a candidate 20 in the examination; and that psychology is one of the three subjects in which he is being examined. The remark might now bear a different meaning—that Jones, having done fairly well on the other two subjects, had ruined his chances of the prize by his bad work on psychology. In other words, psychology is the name both of a science and of the things (or even one specimen of the things) which that science studies.

This transference I call the methodological idiom. It may produce ambiguity: ‘Freud’s psychology’ might mean either a subject of which we have all heard much or one which, some would say, has been examined too little. But ‘my anatomy’ would almost certainly mean those facts about me which an anatomist would speak of as an expert, rather than my theories or proficiency in his science. It would be difficult to explain the word physical if one ignored the methodological idiom. When Milton says in The Reason of Church Government[3] that the Psalms are better than Pindar and Callimachus ‘not in their divine argument alone but in the very critical art of composition’, critical art must surely, by this idiom, mean the art that critics expound; those who practice it are the poets. The curious expression ‘a scientific fact’ may originally have meant a fact that is literally scientific or ‘science-making’—a key fact whose discovery makes possible a wide range of further discoveries. But most modern users, I believe, mean merely ‘a fact of the sort that scientists know about’. The methodological idiom, applied to history, has produced some confusion. It is 21 often hard to be sure whether the word means the past events themselves as they really were or the study that tries to discover and understand them.

VII. MORALISATION OF STATUS-WORDS

Words which originally referred to a person’s rank—to legal, social, or economic status and the qualifications of birth which have often been attached to these—have a tendency to become words which assign a type of character and behaviour. Those implying superior status can become terms of praise; those implying inferior status, terms of disapproval. Chivalrous, courteous, frank, generous, gentle, liberal, and noble are examples of the first; ignoble, villain, and vulgar, of the second.

Sometimes there are complexities. All my life the epithet bourgeois has been, in many contexts, a term of contempt, but not for the same reason. When I was a boy—a bourgeois boy—it was applied to my social class by the class above it; bourgeois meant ‘not aristocratic, therefore vulgar’. When I was in my twenties this changed. My class was now vilified by the class below it; bourgeois began to mean ‘not proletarian, therefore parasitic, reactionary’. Thus it has always been a reproach to assign a man to that class which has provided the world with nearly all its divines, poets, philosophers, scientists, musicians, painters, doctors, architects, and administrators. When the bourgeoisie is despised for not being proletarian we get an exception to the general principle stated above. The name of the higher status implies the worse character and behaviour. This I take to be the peculiar, and transitory, 22 result of a revolutionary situation. The earlier usage—bourgeois as ‘not aristocratic’—is the normal linguistic phenomenon.

It will be diagnosed by many as a symptom of the inveterate snobbery of the human race; and certainly the implications of language are hardly ever egalitarian. But that is not the whole story. Two other factors come in. One is optimism; men’s belief, or at least hope, that their social betters will be personally better as well. The other is far more important. A word like nobility begins to take on its social-ethical meaning when it refers not simply to a man’s status but to the manners and character which are thought to be appropriate to that status. But the mind cannot long consider those manners and that character without being forced on the reflection that they are sometimes lacking in those who are noble by status and sometimes present in those who are not. Thus from the very first the social-ethical meaning, merely by existing, is bound to separate itself from the status-meaning. Accordingly, from Boethius down, it becomes a commonplace of European literature that the true nobility is within, that villanie, not status, makes the villain, that there are ‘ungentle gentles’ and that ‘gentle is as gentle does’. The linguistic phenomenon we are considering is therefore quite as much an escape from, as an assertion of, that pride above and servility below which, in my opinion, should be called snobbery. The behaviour ideally, or optimistically, attributed to an aristocracy provides a paradigm. It becomes obvious that, as regards many aristocrats, this is an unrealised ideal. But the 23 paradigm remains; anyone, even the bad aristocrat himself, may attempt to conform to it. A new ethical idea has come into power.

I think its power has been greatest at that frontier where the aristocrats and the middle class meet. The court takes from the class below it talented individuals—like Chaucer, say—as its entertainers and assistants. We ordinarily think of Chaucer learning his courtesy at court. And no doubt he did; its manners were more graceful than those of his own family. But can we doubt that he also taught courtesy there? By expecting to find realised at court the paradigm of courtesy and nobility, by writing his poetry on the assumption that it was realised, such a man offers a critique—and an unconscious critique—of the court’s actual ethos, which no one can resent. It is not flattery, but it flatters. As they say a woman becomes more beautiful when she is loved, a nobility by status will become more ‘noble’ under such treatment. Thus the Horaces, Chaucers, Racines, or Spensers substantially ennoble their patrons. But also, through them, many graces pass down from the aristocracy into the middle class. This two-way traffic generates a culture-group comprising the choicest members of two groups that differ in status. If this is snobbery, we must reckon snobbery among the greatest nurseries of civilisation. Without it, would there ever have been anything but wealth and power above and sycophancy or envy below?

24

2
NATURE
[WITH PHUSIS, KIND, PHYSICAL ETC.]

In this chapter we shall have to consider Greek phusis, Latin natura (with its derivatives), and English kind. Each of the three has a great number of senses, and two of these senses are common to all of them. One appears to have been reached independently by all three words. The other was at first peculiar to phusis and was thence transferred to natura, and through natura to kind. Thus it is phusis that complicates the whole story, and that story will therefore be most easily told if, in defiance of chronology, we begin with some account of the Latin and English words in their un-hellenised condition, and only after that turn to the Greek.

I. ‘NATURA’

By far the commonest native meaning of natura is something like sort, kind, quality, or character. When you ask, in our modern idiom, what something ‘is like’, you are asking for its natura. When you want to tell a man the natura of anything you describe the thing. In nineteenth-century English the word ‘description’ itself (‘I do not associate with persons of that description’) is often an exact synonym for natura. Caesar sent scouts to find out qualis esset natura montis, what the hill was like, what sort of a hill it was.[4] Quintilian speaks of a man ingenii naturâ praestantem (XII, 1), outstanding by the quality of his 25 mind. Cicero’s title De Natura Deorum could be translated ‘What the gods are like’.

It will be noticed that whereas Caesar wanted to know the (doubtless unique) character of a particular hill, Cicero wrote about the common character of all gods, and Horace[5] can speak of humana natura, the character common to all men. There is a logical distinction here, but linguistically the two usages are the same. A class or species has a natura, and so has a particular or an individual.

It is not always possible, or necessary, to decide whether the idea of the species or that of the particular is uppermost. Cicero says that ‘omnis natura strives to preserve itself’.[6] It makes little difference whether we render omnis natura ‘every class or species’ or ‘every kind (of thing)’, hence ‘a thing of whatever kind’, and hence almost ‘everything’.

Those who wish to go further back will notice that natura shares a common base with nasci (to be born); with the noun natus (birth); with natio (not only a race or nation but the name of the birth-goddess); or even that natura itself can mean the sexual organs—a sense formerly born by English nature, but apparently restricted to the female. It is risky to try to build precise semantic bridges, but there is obviously some idea of a thing’s natura as its original or ‘innate’ character.

If we look forward, the road is clear. This sense of natura, though soon to be threatened by vast semantic growths of another origin, has shown astonishing persistence 26 and is still as current a sense as any other for English nature. Every day we speak about ‘the nature of the case’ (or of the soil, the animal, the problem).

II. ‘KIND’

From the earliest period of our language this has been both a noun (Anglo-Saxon gecynd and cynd) and an adjective (gecynde and cynde).

The meanings of the noun are very close to those of natura. The Anglo-Saxon word can mean what its modern descendant means, a ‘kind’ or sort. Thus wæstma gecynde are ‘kinds’ of fruit, or the rods which had miraculously been turned into gold in Ælfric’s homily on the Assumption of St John can be presently turned back to their former gecynde. The meaning ‘species’, though now archaic, is still familiar to readers of A.V.: ‘every winged fowl after his kind’.[7]

The gecyndlimu or ‘kind-limbs’ are certainly the genitals. When the author of the Anglo-Saxon Phoenix says (l. 355) that God only knows that bird’s gecynde he certainly means its sex. But whether this is the author’s meaning or the word’s meaning may be doubted. He may use gecynde for ‘sex’ only because sex is a kind of kind, nameless and definable only by the context; just as Ælfric in his Grammar uses it for ‘gender’ when he glosses neutrum as ‘neither cynd’. We easily forget how peculiar Latin is in having a special name for this kind of kind; Greek has to make do with genos, and German with Geschlecht.

Kind also means ‘progeny’, ‘offspring’. In Piers Plowman 27 the beasts all ‘follow reason’, show moderation, ‘in etying, in drynking, in gendrynge of kynde’,[8] and there is a curse on all married couples who produce no kynde.[9] Closely linked to this is the larger sense of ‘family’ or ‘stock’; a whole kindred is a kind, as when Jacob in the Middle English Genesis and Exodus left Canaan with many a man of his kinde (ll. 239 f). ‘Gentle kind’ and ‘noble stock’ are almost certainly a doublet of synonyms (like the Prayer Book’s ‘acknowledge and confess’) when Shakespeare writes ‘came of a gentle kind and noble stock’.[10]

Thus the noun, though not historically connected with natura (unless you go back very far indeed), has a tolerably similar semantic area and presents no very serious difficulties. The adjective (gecynde, cynde, cyndelic, kind and kindly) has a more complicated repertory of meanings. It is not possible to reconstruct the bridges between them, still less to be sure in which direction the traffic crossed them. Indeed ‘bridges’ are probably too mechanical an image and the mutual influences between meaning and meaning are as subtle and reciprocal as those between a group of friends.

1. The adjective means ‘hereditary’—the hereditary being, of course, what comes to one in virtue of one’s birth or family (or kind). Thus we are told in Beowulf (l. 2197) that the hero and Hygelac both had gecynde land, hereditary estates, in their native country. Similarly, a kind or kindly lord is one who inherits his lordship. In the Anglo-Saxon Metres of Boethius the Goths are said to have had two gecynde kings.[11] In Malory Arthur tells Launcelot 28 and Bors to go and look after their dead fathers’ lands ‘and cause youre lyege men to know you as for their kynde lord’.[12] Presumably by an extension from this, any thoroughly legitimate lord, as distinct from a conqueror or usurper, may be ‘kindly’. ‘The Red City and all that be therein will take you for their kindly lord.’[13]

It is interesting to notice that the derivatives, both French and English, of Latin naturalis develop the same sense. In Villehardouin’s Conqueste de Constantinople the crusaders present Alexius to the Byzantines as vostre seignor naturel; in Sidney we find ‘your naturall prince’;[14] and in Shakespeare ‘his natural king’.[15] It is most improbable that naturalis could have reached this sense by a native Latin development. But those who knew the noun kind, or its Frankish equivalent, as their word for Latin natura, might come, when they were writing Latin, to think that naturalis would do for the adjective kind.

2. Any behaviour or state which shows a thing’s, or a person’s, kind or nature—which is characteristic of it, typical, normal, and therefore to be expected—may be called ‘kind’. We are told that on a particular occasion Beowulf behaved with valour, as was gecynde to him (l. 2696)—as was ‘just like him’. Malory leaves two lovers in a bed ‘clipping and kissing as was kindly thing’—as of course they would.[16] And here again the sense of the Latin derivative may have been influenced by that of the Germanic word. Naturaliter did not mean ‘of course’, as 29 ‘naturally’ and naturellement often do. This sense is so strangely remote from other senses of ‘naturally’ that we can say ‘As my hostess had cooked it herself, I naturally pretended to like it’. But it becomes easy enough when the original equivalence of gecynd and natura has worked for centuries towards the possible infection of almost any sense of one by almost any sense of the other.

From the idea of the characteristic or normal to that of the proper, the fitting, the desirable, is an easy transition. Indeed the sense-development of the word proper itself, from that which belongs to a thing or makes part of its definition to that which ought to be found in it, is a striking instance. When Philautus says ‘so unkinde a yeare it hath beene . . . that we felt the heate of the Summer before we coulde discerne the temperature of the Spring’,[17] ‘unusual’ would cover all he need mean by unkinde, though one may suspect that some complaint of unfitness or unsuitability goes with it. When Criseyde asks how any plant or living creature can last without ‘his kinde noriture’,[18] it is impossible to draw any distinction between an organism’s characteristic or normal, and its suitable or appropriate, food. But the value judgement is clear, and the sense ‘fitting’ or ‘proper’ is certain when Malory, enumerating the knights who tried to heal Sir Urre, says ‘we must begin at King Arthur, as is kindly to begin at him that was the most man of worship’.[19]

3. Sometimes the adjective has a range of meaning 30 very like that of pius in classical Latin; somewhere between ‘dutiful’ and ‘affectionate’. The man who is pius or ‘kind’ (in this sense) is one who does not good offices in general, but good offices to which close kinship or some other personal relationship binds him. When Sidney speaks of ‘the Paphlagonian unkinde king and his kind son’[20] he means that the father was a very bad (unfatherly) father and the son a very good (filial) son. Here again we shall find the derivative of natura taking on the sense of the Germanic words, so that unnatural and natural mean ‘lacking (or having) due family affection’, and nature itself can mean pietas. Both usages come together when William Bulleyn writes ‘Parents are more natural to their children then children to their fathers and mothers. Nature doth descend but not ascend.’[21] The Latin and English words are used as a doublet by Shakespeare: ‘A brother in his love towards her ever most kind and natural.’[22] But the family (or kind), though the usual, is not the only ground of the special obligation which ‘kindness’ fulfils. Ingratitude is also ‘unkindness’. Sloth, in Piers Plowman, confesses he is ‘unkynde ageyns courtesye’;[23] do him a good turn and he will not respond.

4. The next meaning in our catalogue is closely parallel to that of Latin generosus. If genus is a stock or lineage, generosus ought in logic to mean ‘pertaining to, or having, a lineage’. But in that sense it would be a useless word and to call a man generosus would be to say nothing; for every 31 man has a lineage of some sort. In fact, generosus means well-born, noble, having a good lineage. Similarly when the Germans call a man geboren they mean hoch-geboren, well or nobly born. In just the same way the adjective kind means not ‘having a family or kind’ but ‘noble’. In all three languages one can imagine different routes by which this sense would be reached. When a man advertises his shop as ‘the shop for quality’, he ignores the fact that badness is just as much a quality as goodness; by ‘quality’ he means ‘good quality’. By a similar ellipsis ‘a man of family’ means, or used to mean, ‘a man of good family’. That is one way in which generosus and kind could come to mean not merely ‘familial’ but ‘of a good (noble) family’. Or it might be that certain people were deemed, by earlier societies, to have ‘no family’ in a far more nearly literal sense. The slave, the beggar, the stranger belong to none of the groups which we have been taught, in this settlement, to call families. No doubt (if you come to think of it) they must, in physical fact, have had parents and even grandparents. But not ones we know. They may not even know them themselves. If you ask of which family they come—are they Erlings or Birmings or Wolfings?—the answer is ‘none’. They are outside the organisation we know, as animals are outside it.

By whatever process, kind, then, comes to mean ‘noble’ or ‘gentle’: thus in Genesis and Exodus (l. 1452) we have ‘begotten of kinde blood’. As we should expect—did not our ancestors speak of ‘noble’ and ‘base’ metals?—this can be extended beyond the human sphere, so that one Hales (c. 1656) talks of grafting ‘apples and 32 kind fruit upon thorns’. It is possibly along this branch of meaning that we reach Cleopatra’s ‘kindly creatures, turn all to serpents’[24]—let all the nobler or gentler creatures turn into those we most abhor. The passage in Malory where Percivale helps a lion in its fight against a snake because it is ‘the more naturall beast of the two’ is curious.[25] If ‘more naturall’ means nobler, superior in the supposed social hierarchy of beasts, this will be another instance of the Latin derivative’s semantic infection by the corresponding Germanic word.

Instances of the purely social meaning for kinde are not plentiful. More often (like ‘noble’ itself) it has a vaguely eulogistic sense. Hence ‘kind jeweler’ in Pearl (l. 276), or ‘kinde caroles’ in Gawain (l. 473).

5. The meanings ‘suitable’, pius, and ‘noble’—and especially the last, as the parallel development of gentle shows—may all have played a part in producing that of ‘exorable, compassionate, beneficent—the opposite of cruel’. ‘Each Christian man be kinde to other’, says Langland,[26] meaning, I think, exactly what we should mean now. This is the dangerous sense of the word kind. We may sometimes read it into an old text where it was not intended. In Chaucer’s ‘He was a gentil harlot and a kinde’[27] the modern meaning for both adjectives is probable, but not, I think, certain. In Herbert’s ‘I the unkinde, ungratefull’ (from Love) the modern meaning would be disastrous; the idea of general beneficence from man to God borders on the absurd. Herbert is classing himself 33 with ‘unkind mothers’ and ‘unnatural children’ as one who, with gross insensibility, makes no response to the arch-natural appeal of the tenderest and closest personal relation that can be imagined; one who is loved in vain.

The peculiar erotic use of the word kind is not a special sense but a special application of the sense ‘beneficent or exorable’—especially the latter. The woman who yields to your suit is exorable, therefore kind. Euphemism and gallantry, not always without a touch of irony, probably lie behind this. It must not be hinted that the lady has any passions or senses, and so her favours must be attributed as in the medieval tradition, to mercy, pite, or ore. Hence Collins writes

fair Circassia where, to love inclin’d,

Each swain was bless’d for every maid was kind.[28]

Elsewhere the euphemism almost ceases to be a euphemism and kindness can become a name for (a woman’s) violent sexual passion; so that Dryden, in a startling phrase, speaks of Roman ladies whispering Greek endearments to their lovers ‘in the fury of their kindness’.[29]

III. PHUSIS

(G)nasci and kind have a common root, if you go far enough back. Phusis has quite a different origin. Its representatives, or what seem to be its representatives, in various Indo-Germanic languages suggest two main branches of meaning; the one, something like ‘inhabit, 34 live (at), dwell, remain, be’ (at a place or in a condition); the other, ‘to grow (transitively, as one “grows” cucumbers or a beard, and intransitively as beards and cucumbers grow), to become’. The latter branch is well represented by the Greek verb phuein. Dionysus grows (phuei) the vine for mortals;[30] a father begets (phuei) a son;[31] ‘not to have been born (phunai) has no fellow’, says Sophocles.[32]

The noun phusis can hardly mean anything except ‘beginning, coming-to-be’ when Empedocles says ‘there is neither a phusis nor an end of all mortal things’.[33] On the other hand, it much more often means, like natura or kind, sort or character or ‘description’. ‘A horrid phusis of mind’,[34] ‘the phusis of the Egyptian country’,[35] ‘the philosophic phusis’,[36] are typical. The connection between this and the meaning of the verb phuein is not obvious, though as usual ‘bridges’ can be devised. Aristotle is trying his hand at one in his famous definition; ‘whatever each thing is like (hoion hekaston esti) when its process of coming-to-be is complete, that we call the phusis of each thing’.[37] On this view a thing’s phusis would be what it grows into at maturity.[38] This explanation does not seem to me at all improbable, but Aristotle’s statement is no evidence for it, and Sir David Ross thinks it philologically wrong. Like all philosophers, Aristotle gives words the definitions which will be most useful for his own purpose 35 and the history of his own language is one of the few subjects in which he was not a distinguished pioneer.

But already, before Aristotle wrote, phusis had taken on, in addition to the meaning ‘sort’, a new and quite astonishing sense. The pre-Socratic Greek philosophers had had the idea of taking all the things they knew or believed in—gods, men, animals, plants, minerals, what you will—and impounding them under a single name; in fact, of regarding Everything as a thing, turning this amorphous and heterogeneous collection into an object or pseudo-object. And for some reason the name they chose for it was phusis. Thus in the late sixth or early fifth century we have the great philosophical poem of Parmenides, whose title is everywhere given as About Phusis. In the fifth century we have that of Empedocles About the Phusis tôn ontôn (the Phusis of the things that are).

Why they chose the name phusis is a question to which I can give no confident answer.

We have already noticed that in one of the fragments of Empedocles the word appears to mean ‘a beginning’. This at first sounds hopeful; a work on’ everything’ might possibly be entitled ‘About the Beginning’ or ‘About Becoming’. But not, unfortunately, a work of Empedocles. For in that very fragment he is denying that there are any beginnings, and we know that his whole system excluded them. Growth and change, and every sort of becoming, he regarded as an illusion. Whatever others might do, he of all men could not write a poem about beginning.

36

Another hypothesis would be that phusis sometimes meant for him ‘being’. We have seen that words from the same root can mean something like that in other Indo-Germanic languages. And from what we know about the behaviour of language in general we cannot deny the possibility that this sense, protected from the others by the insulating power of the context, might have occurred, and even lasted for centuries, in Greek. The real difficulty is that it has left no trace. We are inventing, to explain one difficulty, a usage for which we have not a shred of evidence.

A third hypothesis would begin from noticing that Parmenides’ title alone is troublesome. We could explain the Empedoclean ‘About the phusis of the things that are’ and the Lucretian De Rerum Natura. Both could mean ‘What things are like’, and both would be simply two more instances of phusis and natura in the sense ‘character, sort’. If we then assumed that phusis in the title of Parmenides’ poem had originally been followed by a genitive (of things, of all things, of all), the story would become perfectly clear. Men begin by asking what this or that thing is like, asking for its phusis. They then get the idea of asking what ‘everything’ or ‘the whole show’ is like. The answer will give the phusis of everything. By an ellipse, the qualifying genitive then comes to be omitted, and the word which originally meant ‘sort’, in certain contexts, and protected by those contexts, comes to mean ‘everything’ or the universe. All this, I believe, could have happened; I am not claiming to know that it did.

However it came about, the amazing leap was made. 37 A comparatively small number of speculative Greeks invented Nature—Nature with a capital, nature (d.s.) or nature in the dangerous sense, for of all the senses of all the words treated in these pages this is surely the most dangerous, the one we are readiest to intrude where it is not required. From phusis this meaning passed to natura and from natura to kind. All three become names for what in China (I am told) is called ‘the ten thousand things’.

Linguistically nature (d.s.) is more important for the slightly different senses which it led into than for any great use which was made of it in its purity. Nature (d.s.), if taken strictly, has no opposite. When we say that any particular thing is part of nature (d.s.), we know no more about it than before. ‘Everything’ is a subject on which there is not much to be said. Perhaps the chief use of nature (d.s.) in its purity is as the grammatical subject for expressions of optimism or pessimism: it is in that way rather like the word life.

But when nature (d.s.) loses its purity, when it is used in a curtailed or ‘demoted’ sense, it becomes important.

Parmenides and Empedocles had thought that they were giving, in principle, an account of everything. Later thinkers denied this; not in the sense that they wanted to add particular items here and there, but in the sense that they believed in realities of a quite different order from any that their predecessors took account of. They expressed this not in the form ‘phusis contains more than our ancestors supposed’, but in the form (explicitly or implicitly), ‘there is something else besides phusis’. The 38 moment you say this, phusis is being used in what I call its demoted sense. For it had meant ‘everything’ and you are now saying there is something in addition to it. You are in fact using phusis to mean ‘all the sort of things which our predecessors believed to be the only things’. You are also executing a movement of thought which would have been very much more difficult if those predecessors had not already impounded all those things in a single noun and, in fact, made the mere aggregate into what seemed to be an object with a determinate character of its own. Once that had been done it was possible, and convenient, to use the word phusis for that object, now no longer equated with everything. The ‘demoted d.s.’ presupposes and profits by, the pure d.s. By (so to speak) inventing Nature the old thinkers had made possible, or at least facilitated, the question whether there is anything else.

There were three principal movements towards demotion.

1. The Platonic. In Platonism, as everyone knows, the whole perceptible universe in space and time is an imitation, and product, of something different: the imperceptible, timeless, archetypal forms. This product or imitation, since it contains all the things which the older writers include in phusis, easily comes to be itself called phusis; as when Plotinus says that the arts imitate, not sensible objects, but those principles (logoi) from which phusis itself proceeds.[39] It is a demoted phusis because, far from being all that is, it is far less real and valuable than the realm of forms.

39

2. The Aristotelian. Aristotle criticised thinkers like Parmenides because ‘they never conceived of anything other than the substance of things perceptible by the senses’.[40] Phusis he defines as that which has in itself a principle of change. It is the subject-matter of natural (phusike) philosophy. (This is illuminating. We are getting to the age of universities and phusis (d.s.) demoted can be defined as the ‘subject’ of a particular discipline. Soon, in a new sense, everyone will ‘know what phusis is’: it is what so-and-so lectures on. The methodological idiom thus gets to work.) But there are two things outside phusis. First, things which are unchangeable, but cannot exist ‘on their own’. These are the subject-matter of mathematics. Secondly, there is one thing which is unchangeable and does exist on its own. This is God, the unmoved mover; and he is studied by a third discipline.[41] On him ‘the sky and all phusis depend’;[42] words reproduced by Dante in Paradiso XXVIII, 41.

3. The Christian. Christianity involves a God as transcendent as Aristotle’s, but adds (this was what it inherited from Judaism and could also have inherited from Plato’s Timaeus) the conception that this God is the Creator of phusis. Nature (d.s.) demoted is now both distinct from God and also related to him as artifact to artist, or as servant to master; so that God in Tasso has natura under his feet.[43]

In the Middle Ages a still further demotion or restriction occurred, by which nature no longer covered the 40 whole even of the created universe. Nature’s realm was supposed to extend only as far upwards as the orbit of the moon.[44] That may lend an unsuspected precision to the words which Chaucer puts into the mouth of nature personified.

Eche thing in my cure is

Under the Mone that mai waxe and wane.[45]

Childish as this particular demotion may sound, it goes back to a respectable division between the sublunary and the translunary which Aristotle made in order to cover what observation seemed, in his time, to show.[46] Even in the passage already quoted, it will be remembered, not only phusis but ‘the sky and phusis’ hung upon God.[47]

When we emphasise the idea that nature is a divine artifact, we get yet another contrast. Pagan myths (you will find them in the first book of Ovid’s Metamorphoses) and Genesis seemed to agree that matter first existed in a state of disorder (tohu-bohu or chaos) and was afterwards ordered and worked up into a kosmos (kosmein, to arrange, organise, embellish, whence also cosmetics). The cosmos can then be called nature and contrasted with the preceding—and perhaps subsequent—disorder. Hence Milton describes chaos as ‘the womb of Nature and perhaps her grave’.[48]

But besides all these demotions there was also apotheosis. This would perhaps have been hardly possible before nature (d.s.) had been named, and seems wholly 41 foreign to the spirit of the earliest Greek mythology.[49] But once you can talk about nature (d.s.) you can deify it—or ‘her’. Hence the sense which I shall call Great Mother Nature; nature used to mean not simply all the things there are, as an aggregate or even a system, but rather some force or mind or élan supposed to be immanent in them. It is of course often impossible to be sure in a given instance whether the sense Great Mother Nature implied genuine personalisation (a deity believed in) or merely personification as a rhetorical figure. When Cicero says that Cleanthes gave the name of God to the mind and spirit of all natura[50] it is almost certainly the former. But when he says ‘What workman save Natura could have attained such skill?’[51] it might be not much more than a figure. When Marcus Aurelius, or any sound Stoic, calls Phusis ‘the eldest of deities’ (IX, 1), I think this is the language of actual religion; about the natura who appears in Statius’ Thebaid I am in doubt. But the kinde[52] or natura and physis[53] or nature,[54] the ‘vicaire of the almightie Lorde’,[55] who so dominates medieval poetry, is a personification, though a very grave and active one.

Great Mother Nature has proved a most potent sense down to the present day. It is ‘she’ who does nothing by leaps, abhors a vacuum, is die gute Mutter, is red in tooth and claw, ‘never did betray the heart that loved her’, 42 eliminates the unfit, surges to ever higher and higher forms of life, decrees, purposes, warns, punishes and consoles. Even now I am not sure that this meaning is always used purely as a figure, to say what would equally make sense without it. The test is to remove the figure and see how much sense remains. Of all the pantheon Great Mother Nature has, at any rate, been the hardest to kill.

IV. ‘NATURE’ AND ITS OPPOSITES

The sense we have just been considering might seem so overwhelming that, once reached, it would dominate, or perhaps devour, all other senses of the word. But we daily prove that this is not so by speaking of ‘the nature of the case’ or ‘a good-natured man’ when there is before our mind no idea of nature (d.s.), strict or demoted, personified or literal. For the hierarchy of meanings is not like the hierarchy of things. That sense of the word which refers to the most ancient thing need not be the most ancient sense; that which refers to an all-embracing thing need not be the all-embracing sense. The thing we mean by nature (d.s.) may be the trunk on which we all grow; the sense nature (d.s.) is by no means the semantic trunk on which all the meanings grow. It is itself only one of the branches. Hence we shall go widely astray if we assume that whenever authors use the word nature they must be thinking of nature (d.s.). Especially, we shall go astray if we think that all uses of the word nature which carry approval indicate an optimistic, and all disapproving usages a pessimistic, view of nature (d.s.). These usages may have a different source and need imply no view of 43 nature (d.s.) at all. Of course the hovering presence of nature (d.s.) in the background often moulds the rhetorical form, and sometimes even modifies the thought when the author is saying things which (fundamentally) require different senses.

The best clue is to ask oneself in each instance, what is the implied opposite to nature, and a list of such opposites will now occupy us for some pages. Their very existence proves how little the sense nature (d.s.) (which has no opposite) is involved.

V. ‘NATURAL AND UNNATURAL’

There are two chief branches.

1. Since natural can mean ‘having due affection’, or pius, unnatural (as already noticed) of course means the reverse. Thus old Hamlet’s ghost says that, while all murder is ‘most foul’, his own murder was ‘strange and unnatural’, because it was fratricidal.

2. Anything which has changed from its sort or kind (nature) may be described as unnatural, provided that the change is one the speaker deplores. Behaviour is unnatural or ‘affected’, not simply when it is held to be a departure from that which a man’s nature would lead to of itself, but when it is a departure for the worse. When the timid man forces himself to be brave, or the choleric man to be just, he is not called unnatural. ‘Unnatural vices’ are so called because the appetite has exchanged its characteristic and supposedly original bent, its phusis, for one which most men think worse. (Perpetual continence, though equally a departure from the phusis, would be, and is, 44 called unnatural only by those who disapprove of it.) It is just possible that the Great Mother Nature meaning has had an influence here, for in medieval personifications of her she is very apt to talk about fertility, and the ‘plaint’ which she makes in Alanus ab Insulis’ De Planctu Naturae is one against homosexuality. But I do not think this at all probable.

Why unnatural should always (as unearthly is not) be a term of reprobation is not easy to understand. The strongly pejorative force of its first usage (lacking in due affection) may have something to do with it.

It is sufficiently obvious that neither sense is derived from nature (d.s.) which of course includes fratricide and perversion as it includes everything else.

VI. THE ‘NATURAL’ AND THE INTERFERED WITH

A beautifully pure example of this sense occurs in Chaucer. Medieval astronomers believed that the lower heavenly spheres had an inherent impulse to move from west to east, but that the Primum Mobile, moving from east to west, forced them backwards in that direction. Chaucer complains that the ‘firste moeving cruel firmament’ thus forces westward all those things ‘that naturelly wolde holde another way’.[56] Now of course both movements are equally within nature (d.s.). But Chaucer is not thinking of nature (d.s.). Nor are we while we read his line. His usage is still so familiar and intelligible that we all know at once, without having to think about it, what he means by ‘would naturally’; he means ‘would spontaneously, of their own accord, if they were let alone’. 45 Similarly, we feel no difficulty when Aristotle says ‘We must study what is natural (phusei) in specimens which are in their natural condition (kata phusin), not in those which have been damaged’.[57]

This, as it is one of the oldest, is one of the hardiest senses of nature or natural. The nature of anything, its original, innate character, its spontaneous behaviour, can be contrasted with what it is made to be or do by some external agency. A yew-tree is natural before the topiarist has carved it; water in a fountain is forced upwards against its nature; raw vegetables are au naturel. The natural here is the Given.

This distinction between the uninterfered with and the interfered with will not probably recommend itself to philosophers. It may be held to enshrine a very primitive, an almost magical or animistic, conception of causality. For of course in the real world everything is continuously ‘interfered with’ by everything else; total mutual interference (Kant’s ‘thorough-going reciprocity’) is of the essence of nature (d.s.). What keeps the contrast alive, however, is the daily experience of men as practical, not speculative, beings. The antithesis between unreclaimed land and the cleared, drained, fenced, ploughed, sown, and weeded field—between the unbroken and the broken horse—between the fish as caught and the fish opened, cleaned, and fried—is forced upon us every day. That is why nature as ‘the given’, the thing we start from, the thing we have not yet ‘done anything about’, is such a persistent sense. We here, of course, means man. If ants 46 had a language they would, no doubt, call their anthill an artifact and describe the brick wall in its neighbourhood as a natural object. Nature in fact would be for them all that was not ‘ant-made’. Just so, for us, nature is all that is not man-made; the natural state of anything is its state when not modified by man. This is one source of the antithesis (philosophically so scandalous) between nature and Man. We as agents, as interferers, inevitably stand over against all the other things; they are all raw material to be exploited or difficulties to be overcome. This is also a fruitful source of favourable and unfavourable overtones. When we deplore the human interferences, then the nature which they have altered is of course the unspoiled, the uncorrupted; when we approve them, it is the raw, the unimproved, the savage.

Inevitably this contrast is represented in all the languages we have had to consider. Things may be in a satisfactory condition either by nature (phusei) or by art (techne), in Plato.[58] A death which occurs of itself, without external violence, is a natural (kata phusin) death. The peasant to whom Electra had been, outrageously, married, abstained from her bed for various reasons, one being that he was naturally (ephu) chaste; not through fear, nor by painful efforts of resolution—he was ‘that sort of man’.[59] Quintilian says that in oratory natura can do much without training but training can do little without natura (II, xix). The nature in question is of course the ‘given’ capacity in the pupil, what the teacher finds to work upon. Addison speaks of the ‘rustic part of the species who on all occasions 47 acted bluntly and naturally’:[60] no efforts of their own had modified their given behaviour (given by temperament, environment, and the passions) in the direction either of refinement or affectation.

This contrast easily accommodates, without substantial change of what is being said, allusions to Great Mother Nature; as in Milton’s description of the paradisal flowers

which not nice Art

In Beds and curious knots, but nature boon

Pourd forth profuse[61]

Sometimes it is difficult to say whether Great Mother Nature, even rhetorically, is intended or not. Sannazaro, in the Proem to his Arcadia, prefers to the products of the gardener’s art the trees on the rude mountains ‘brought forth by nature’ (de la natura produtti). Is natura here intended to arouse the image of the Great Mother, or does it only mean naturally? Seneca says ‘for natura does not give virtue; it is an art to become good’.[62] It might mean simply ‘We are not born with all the virtues, they don’t come of their own accord. We have to work at them.’ On the other hand, he was a Stoic and Great Mother Nature was very often in his mind. It is of course very possible that neither he nor Sannazaro could have answered the question or had ever raised it.

VII. THE ‘NATURAL’ AS AN ELEMENT IN MAN

I divide this class into three sub-classes and must give warning that I am in some doubt about all of them except 48 the first. The second I am not sure that I have understood; the third, for a reason which will appear, is bound to have an uncertain fringe. I think it better to give the reader even a dubious classification (which he can then pull to pieces for himself) than a jungle of miscellanea at the end.

1. Speaking of worldly goods Boethius says that natura is content with few of them.[63] Alfred, correctly, translates ‘in very little of them kind (gecynd) has enough’. Spenser, probably with the Boethian passage in mind, remarks ‘with how small allowance Untroubled Nature doth herself suffice’.[64] When Adam and Eve and the Archangel dined together they ate what ‘sufficed, not burdened nature’.[65] The implied contrast in all these is between what the nature of man wants—what a man wants simply in virtue of being the kind of organism he is—and what this or that man learns to want by being luxurious, fanciful, or fashionable. This would be an application of the more general contrast of nature as the given against the interfered with. Our ‘built in’ appetites are interfered with by our individual ways of life.

2. But what are we to make of the following usages? A natural is an idiot or imbecile. ‘Love is like a great natural that runs lolling up and down to hide his bauble in a hole.’[66] Again, the unconscious vital powers in a man’s body can be nature. ‘Ther nature wol not wirche’, says Chaucer of the dying Arcite, ‘Far-wel Physik! Go bear the man to chirche’.[67] Most startling of all, Dryden’s 49 Abdalla says ‘Reason’s a staff for age when nature’s gone’.[68] We could, at a pinch, get rid of the Chaucerian passage. Nature in it might be Great Mother Nature refusing to work in one man’s body. The two other specimens are alike in suggesting a contrast between nature and reason. The idiot is a natural for lacking it, and Abdalla will not use it as long as he has nature instead. Now, since the nature of man was defined as ‘rational animal’, it seems very odd that the absence, or opposite, of reason in him should be natural.

The explanation I would suggest is as follows. We have already seen how the contrast between nature and man arises from our practical life. But it was also reinforced from another direction. Man is represented both in the Timaeus and in Genesis as the subject of a separate and special creation; as something added, by a fresh act of God, to the rest of nature (d.s.) demoted. (In Bernardus and in the Anticlaudian of Alanus the creation of man becomes even more special and more separate.) And of course ‘the rest of Nature’ could easily, in opposition to Man, be called simply nature. It could therefore be felt that what man shares with (the rest of) nature, what he has only because he is a creature and not because he is a special creature, is natural in contradistinction to his specific, specially created, differentia. Thus, paradoxically but not unintelligibly, man could be most natural (most united with the rest of nature) in those states and activities which are least rational. And we may perhaps add to this that the specifically human, the exercise and domination of 50 reason, is achieved in each man only by effort. The state of a man before reason has developed in him, or while reason is in abeyance, may therefore be natural also in the sense of being ‘given’—being what happens if nothing is done about it. The idiot has only remained in the state of irrationality in which we all began. Abdalla identifies nature either with passion itself or with the dominance of passion because passion both arises and rules us unless we ‘interfere’ with ourselves.

Along these lines the word nature could reach the sense ‘that in man which is not specifically human, that which he shares with the animals’. Hence such euphemisms as ‘a call of nature’. Hence, as perhaps in the Chaucerian passage, the unconscious processes (digestion, circulation etc.) could be nature.

3. Here I feel pretty confident that the class I am discussing is a real class; but one older meaning of nature makes it doubtful whether certain instances fall within it or not. We have seen that nature can mean ‘due affection’ or pietas. Thus there are two possible ways of taking the ghost’s words to Hamlet ‘If thou hast nature in thee, bear it not’ (I, v, 81), and Prospero’s ‘You, brother mine that entertained ambition, expelled remorse and nature’ (v, i, 75). The ghost might mean ‘if you have any filial feelings’; Prospero might mean ‘You expelled all the feelings of a brother’. But equally the ghost might mean ‘If you still retain the nature of a man, if you have not departed from the human phusis’. And Prospero might mean ‘You drove out the given nature of humanity, voluntarily depraved yourself from your kind.’ I suspect the first explanation 51 is the more likely for these passages. (Both senses might of course be present, or the distinction might never have been consciously before Shakespeare’s mind.) But the second seems more probable when Lady Macbeth prays that ‘no compunctious visitings of nature’ may shake her fell purpose (I, v, 45). She might possibly be praying that the ‘due affection’ and loyalty which she owes to Duncan as king, guest, kinsman, and benefactor, should not visit her with compunction. But, taken in connection with ‘unsex me here’, nature seems more likely to mean ‘my original datum of human nature’. She is deliberately casting out, and forbidding to return, her womanhood, her humanity, her reason (as our ancestors understood the word reason).

Nature here appears as good because the creature is departing from its phusis for something worse. This has nothing to do with an optimistic view of human nature in general, much less of nature (d.s.). We can interfere with our given nature either to mend or to mar it; we can climb above it or sink below it. Thus in a man who is depraving himself his nature will be the only trace of good still left in him (his form has not yet lost all her original brightness). Later, it will be the good he has finally lost. But when a man is growing better, rising above or (as we say) ‘conquering’ his original psychological datum, nature will be relatively bad—the element in him still unconquered or uncorrected. Banquo is a good man, but he has to pray ‘Merciful powers, Restrain in me the cursed thoughts that nature gives way to in repose’ (II, i, 7). The original human datum in him is not yet so conquered that 52 it cannot raise its head in his dreams.[69] Thus Johnson can say ‘We are all envious naturally but by checking envy we get the better of it.[70] Pope’s usage is more complex—a good subject for Professor Empson—when he makes Eloisa say

Then Conscience sleeps and, leaving Nature free,

All my loose soul unbounded leaps to thee.[71]

From the point of view of her pious resolutions nature here is the given which ought to be conquered and whose persistence is therefore bad. But she probably also pleads by implication that her passion for Abelard is after all natural and therefore excusable (a usage we must return to); natural as ordinary, to be expected, and also perhaps as something authoritatively sanctioned or irresistibly imposed by Great Mother Nature. The idea that sexual desire is natural because it is not specifically human may also come in.

My examples so far have all been ethical, the natural element in a man appearing as something morally better or worse than what he may make of it. But it can be contrasted as ‘given’ with things which are not, in the context, regarded as obligatory or culpable. An example (despite the borrowing of a religious term in it) is Coleridge’s

And happly by abstruse research to steal

From my own nature all the natural man.[72]

Coleridge was determining, like Lady Macbeth, to depart from his phusis, but not (on most views) to deprave it. 53 We get the same non-moral contrast, complicated by Great Mother Nature, in this from Tristram Shandy (V, iii): ‘When Tully was bereft of his daughter at first he listened to the voice of nature and modulated his own unto it . . . O my Tullia, my daughter, my child . . . But as soon as he began to look into the stores of philosophy and consider how many excellent things might be said upon the occasion . . . no body on earth can conceive, says the great orator, how joyful it made me.’ ‘Voice’ here brings in the personification; but substantially the contrast is between the given—what Cicero, what anyone, would spontaneously feel—and what philosophy and rhetoric (conceived by Sterne as affectations) could make out of it.

VIII. ‘NATURE’ AND GRACE

Banquo’s evening prayer brought us already to the frontier of this class. Human nature (man as he is of himself) can be contrasted not only, as above, with man as he can become by moral effort but with man as he can be refashioned by divine grace. The antithesis is now not merely moral. ‘The loss of my husband’, says Christiana, ‘came into my mind, at which I was heartily grieved; but all that was but natural affection’.[73] What is here depreciated or discounted as ‘but natural’ is nothing depraved or sub-human; on the contrary, it is something, on its own level and in its own mode, lawful, commanded, entirely good. But it involves none of the new motives, the new perspective, the revaluation of all things, which, on the Christian view go with conversion. It does not 54 (in most theologies) need to be repented of; but neither does it indicate ‘the New Man’. It is therefore merely nature, not grace—or not of faith, or not spiritual. Often of course, this contrast is merely implicit:

see, sons, what things you are!

How quickly nature falls into revolt

When gold becomes her object![74]

The choice of the word nature, in the context, would in Shakespeare’s time have made the theological implication clear. Nature means ‘we human beings in our natural condition’, that is, unless or until touched by grace. This is what ‘Nature’ means as the title of one of Herbert’s poems. It is about the element of untransformed, ungraced human nature in the poet—his Old Man, Old Adam, his vetustas, full of rebellion and venom, untamed, precarious, and perishing. The classic place for this contrast is the Imitation (III, liv): ‘Diligently watch the motions of nature and of grace . . . nature is subtle and always has self for end . . . grace walks in sincerity and does all for God.’ In the next chapter the author adds a linguistic note: ‘for nature is fallen and so the very word nature (though she was created good and right) now means the weakness of fallen nature.’

IX. NATURE AND THE MIMETIC ARTS

The contrasts we have hitherto been considering are all really variations upon a single contrast; that of nature as the given or uninterfered with, over against what has 55 been, for better or worse, made of it. We now come to a different contrast; the nature of a thing as its real character, over against what it is thought to be or represented as being or treated as if it were.

Thus poets and painters are said to be imitating nature. Nature in this context primarily means the real character (the phusis or what-sortedness) of the things they are representing. When the horses in your picture are like real horses or the lovers in your comedy behave like real lovers, then of course your work is ‘true to nature’ or ‘natural’. And just as we call the painted shapes ‘horses’ and the dramatic personages ‘lovers’, so the correct depiction of them in the mimetic work can itself be called nature. Thus Pope can speak of a work ‘Where nature moves and rapture warms the mind’;[75] or Johnson can complain ‘In this poem there is no nature for there is no truth.’[76]

A full account of nature as a term in neo-classical criticism would require a whole book and will not, of course, be attempted here. But two points must be made.

1. Some of those who were neo-classical critics held optimistic views about nature (d.s.) and willingly used the figure of Great Mother Nature. But their frequent eulogies on nature in works of art are not necessarily connected with this. They may be emotionally tinged by it, or the writers themselves may sometimes be confused. But in logic, if your theory of art is mimetic, then of course you must praise artists for ‘following’ nature and blame them for departing from it—must praise nature in a work of art and censure the absence of nature—whatever 56 you think about nature (d.s.). An imitation must be judged by its resemblance to the model.

2. We have already learned from Aristotle that the phusis of anything is ‘what it is like when its process of coming to be is complete’.[77] We have learned also from Aristotle, that we must ‘study what is natural from specimens which are in their natural condition, not from damaged ones’.[78] An immature or deformed specimen does not display its phusis accurately. Now if you once get (from Aristotle’s Poetics and Horace’s De Arte) the theory that art imitates the general, not the individual, that the nature to be imitated is really the natures of whole classes (horses, lovers), then the same principles apply to art as to biology. This doctrine of generality was of course widely held in the neo-classical period; ‘nothing can please many and please long’ except by ‘just representations of general nature’.[79] It would have been clearer[80] if he had said ‘general natures’. Obviously you can depict the general nature of a class only by displaying it in a fully developed, normal, undeformed specimen. The general nature of feet is not revealed by a drawing, however accurate, of a club foot (though of course club feet are an item in nature (d.s.)). The general nature of pedlars is not revealed by Wordsworth’s portrait of the Wanderer in 57 The Excursion (though of course it is not strictly impossible that nature (d.s.) should once have included an individual pedlar who was just like him).

This view explains some otherwise unintelligible statements by Thomas Rymer. ‘Nature knows nothing in the manners which so properly distinguishes woman as doth her modesty’.[81] This does not mean that Rymer is so simple as to deny the existence of immodest women. He knows perfectly well that nature (d.s.) includes immodest women, as it includes bearded women, hunchbacks and homosexuals. But they are not specimens in which we can observe general female nature. He makes this quite clear by adding ‘if a woman has got any accidental historical impudence’ (i.e. immodesty, impudicitia) ‘she must no longer stalk in Tragedy . . . but must rub off and pack down with the carriers into the Provence of Comedy’.[82] She is proper in comedy (no doubt) because its corrective function is precisely to pillory aberrations from (general) nature. But female ‘impudence’ is no matter for serious poetry because, though it certainly occurs in nature (d.s.), when it does so it is merely ‘accidental’ (in the logical sense) and ‘historical’. That is, it merely records the particular, which, as Aristotle had taught, is the function of history, not of tragedy.[83] It is in the light of this that we must understand his notorious remark about Iago. He condemns Iago for being an ‘insinuating rascal’ instead of a ‘plain-dealing souldier’—‘a character constantly worn 58 by them for thousands of years in the World’.[84] Rymer is not in the least denying that such a soldier as Iago could exist; the point is that, if he did, he would be a mere historical accident, not instructive as to the general nature of soldiers, and therefore improper in tragedy.

It will be seen that this demand for the typical easily merges into a demand for the perfect. The quest for the wholly normal cabbage—as we significantly say ‘the perfect specimen’—would involve the rejection of every cabbage which had suffered from such historical accidents as bad soil, unequal sun (and therefore different growth) on this side and that, too much or too little rain, and so on. In the end you would be looking for the ideal cabbage. This development, I suspect, is more easily seen in the criticism of painting. But Rymer is moving in that direction when he says that ‘no shadow of sense can be pretended for bringing any wicked persons on the stage’.[85] I fear he was encouraged by Aristotle’s strange maxim that the characters in a tragedy should, before everything else, be ‘good’.[86]

X. BY ‘NATURE’ OR BY LAW

Here, as in the preceding contrast, nature is the actual. What a thing is in its own nature and therefore really is, is set against what law (or custom, or convention) treats it as being. The claims made by women when the suffragist movement began, or by native Africans in parts of Africa, could in traditional language have taken the form 59 ‘Our inferiority to you (men or whites) is legal or conventional, not natural’. A good example is the discussion on slavery in the first book of Aristotle’s Politics. Aristotle thought that some men were specially qualified by their character to be slaves and others to be masters. The one sort were therefore natural slaves, the other natural masters. But of course the actual working of the slave trade, which gets its livestock by kidnapping, purchase, or capture in war, did not at all insure that only the natural slaves were enslaved. (He oddly ignores the equally obvious truth that those who own slaves will often not be natural masters.) We must therefore distinguish the natural from the legal slave: him who ought to be, who is fit only to be, a slave, from him who is a slave in the eyes of the law.

Again, it must have been a primeval question whether what your father, or teacher, or king, or the laws of your country declared to be just or right was ‘really’ just or right. Linguistic analysts may (and what a comfort that will be to all governments!) succeed in convincing the world that the expression ‘really right’ is meaningless; but for millennia it was accepted as full of meaning. The idea of the ‘really right’, as against the law of the political ruler, is expressed in its purity by Sophocles through the mouth of Antigone: ‘I did not think your proclamation of such force that you, a man, destined to die, should override the laws of the gods, unwritten and unvarying. For those are not of yesterday nor of today, but everlasting. No one knows when they began.’[87]

60

In plain prose the antithesis takes the following form. Someone in Plato’s Gorgias (482e) speaks of things ‘which are laudable (kala) not by phusis but by law or convention (nomô)’. Or Cicero says ‘If, as it is naturally (naturâ), so it were in men’s thoughts, and each regarded nothing human as alien from him’.[88] Plato’s phusis could here be rendered ‘really’: Cicero’s natura ‘in reality’. But such thoughts lead to a new usage which has, historically, been more important even than the conception of nature (d.s.). We can see it beginning in another passage from the Gorgias: ‘They do these things according to the phusis of justice and, by heaven, according to the law of phusis, though perhaps not according to the law we men lay down’ (483e).

Notice, first, that an abstract like Justice (at least, it is an abstract for modern thought) can now have its phusis. This I take to be a consequence of asking whether the state’s ‘justice’ is real justice or not. For this seems to imply that the question ‘What’s justice like—really like?’ is significant; and what would you then be asking about if not about the real phusis of justice?

Secondly, we now have the conception ‘law of phusis’. I am not at all sure what Plato meant by this second phusis; but it would seem at least to mean ‘reality’. The law of reality would be the real law. But is he also bringing in something of nature (d.s.) or of Great Mother Nature? (His own particular demotion of nature (d.s.) is not relevant at this point.)

However that may be, the way is now open to the gigantic antithesis (ancient, medieval, and early modern) 61 between natural and civil law; the unchangeable and universal law of nature and the varying law of this or that state. But the ambiguity of the word nature allowed men to use this antithesis for the expression of very different political philosophies.

On the one hand, if nature is thought of mainly as the real (opposed to convention and legal fiction) and the laws of nature as those which enjoin what is really good and forbid what is really bad (as opposed to the pseudo-duties which bad governments praise and reward or the real virtues which they forbid and punish), then of course ‘the law of nature’ is conceived as an absolute moral standard against which the laws of all nations must be judged and to which they ought to conform. It will be in fact the sort of thing Antigone was talking about. Great Mother Nature may well come in at this point but she will be either, for Stoics, a deified Mother Nature, or, for Christians, a Mother Nature who is the ‘vicaire of the almightie lord’, inscribing her laws, which she learned from God, on the human heart. This is the conception of natural Law that underlies the work of Thomas Aquinas, Hooker and Grotius.

On the other hand nature may mean nature (d.s.), and even with a special emphasis on the non-human parts of it (the obstinate contrast of Nature and man helps here) or, within man, on those motives and modes of behaviour which are least specifically human. The ‘laws of Nature’ on this view are inferred from the way in which non-human agents always behave, and human agents behave until they are trained not to. Thus what Aquinas or 62 Hooker would call ‘the law of Nature’ now becomes in its turn the convention; it is something artificially imposed, in opposition to the true law of nature, the way we all spontaneously behave if we dare (or don’t interfere with ourselves), the way all the other creatures behave, the way that comes ‘naturally’ to us. The prime law of nature, thus conceived, is self-preservation and self-aggrandisement, pursued by whatever trickeries or cruelties may prove to be advisable. This is Hobbes’s Natural Law.

XI. THE STATE OF ‘NATURE’ AND THE CIVIL STATE

On either of these views civil law is man-made and natural law is not. The one is a contrivance, the other a given; so that this contrast, though it seems to begin in that of real and conventional, slides back into the more familiar one of the raw (or unspoiled) and the improved (or sophisticated). That was perhaps why nearly all political thinkers except Aristotle assumed that men had once lived without social organisation and obeyed no laws except those (whatever those were) of nature. That pre-civil condition was described as nature or ‘the state of nature’. This too, of course, might be conceived in opposite ways. It might be a primeval innocence from which our transition to the civil state was a fall. ‘The first of mortals and their children followed nature, uncorrupted, and enjoyed the nature of things in common’, says Seneca.[89] The ‘nature of things’ which they enjoyed is 63 nature (d.s.). The nature they followed is primarily their own, still unspoiled, phusis. But they enjoyed ‘the nature of things in common’ because civil government and private property had not yet been contrived—not while they were in the state of nature. So Pope:

Nor think in Nature’s state they blindly trod;

The state of Nature was the reign of God.[90]

On the other hand it could be conceived of as the state of savagery to escape from which we had contrived the civil state, finding that in the state of nature man’s life was, as Hobbes said, ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short’.[91]

The state of nature which (it was thought) had preceded civil society, and would return if civil society were abolished, still in a sense underlies it. Government is supposed to do for us certain things we should have done for ourselves in the state of nature; it can be maintained that where it fails to do any of them we are, as regards those things, still in the state of nature and may act accordingly. Johnson says that a man whose father’s murderer, by a peculiarity of Scotch Law, has escaped hanging, might reasonably say ‘I am among barbarians who refuse to do justice. I am therefore in a state of nature and consequently . . . I will stab the murderer of my father.’[92]

It should be noticed that the expression ‘state of nature’ is sometimes borrowed from its proper political context and given a meaning which really attaches it to our 64 section VI. It may be used to mean not the pre-civil but the pre-civilised; the condition of man, not without government, but without arts, inventions, learning, and luxury. Thus in another part of his Hebrides Boswell records ‘our satisfaction at finding ourselves again in a comfortable carriage was very great. We laughed at those who attempted to persuade us of the superior advantages of a state of nature.’[93] The ‘state of nature’ here means ponies and mountain tracks as against carriages and metalled roads. He even uses nature by itself in what I take to be the same sense when he speaks of wishing ‘to live three years in Otaheite and be satisfied what pure nature can do for man’.[94]

XII. ‘NATURAL’ AND ‘SUPERNATURAL’

1. In its strict theological sense this distinction presents little difficulty. When any agent is empowered by God to do that of which its own kind or nature would never have made it capable, it is said to act super-naturally, above its nature. The story in which Balaam’s ass speaks is a story of the supernatural because speech is not a characteristic of asinine nature. When Isaiah saw the seraphim he saw supernaturally because human eyes are not by their own nature qualified to see such things. Of course examples of the supernatural need not be, like these, spectacular. Whatever a man is enabled to receive or do by divine grace, and not by the exercise of his own nature, is supernatural. Hence ‘ioy, peace and delight’ (of a certain sort) can be described by Hooker as ‘supernaturall 65 passions’ (I, xi, 3). If this were the only sense the word bore, I should of course have mentioned it above when we were dealing with nature and grace. Unfortunately it has others.

2. We have already noticed that Aristotle speaks about things being ‘in their natural condition’: i.e. not damaged, or otherwise interfered with. But things can be changed from this natural condition: changed, in that sense, from their nature. A farmer can give a pig a degree of fatness which its nature, unaided, would never have achieved. It would then be fat ‘above (its) nature’. Illness can raise a man’s temperature higher than in his natural (normal, unimpaired) condition it would rise. To call him then supernaturally hot would now be startling, but the word could once, and quite intelligibly, be so used. Elyot says ‘Unnaturall or supernaturall heate destroyeth appetite’.[95] In The Flower and the Leaf (l. 413) ‘Unkindly hete’ means, with some hyperbole, feverishness, pathological heat.

3. But neither of these senses is very close to that which supernatural bears in modern, untheological English. Why is a ghost called supernatural? Certainly not because it stands outside nature (d.s.). The proper word for ‘outside nature (d.s.)’ is ‘non-existent’. But that cannot be what supernatural means, for it would be used of ghosts equally by those who believe and those who disbelieve in them. Nor does anyone call phlogiston supernatural. You could of course make ‘demotions’ of nature (d.s.) which would exclude the ghost, but they would have to be artificially contrived for that express purpose. The Platonic one 66 would not do, for ghosts, being particulars, could not be in the realm of forms; nor the Aristotelian, for ghosts are not God, nor are they mathematical concepts; nor the Christian, for they are creatures. It is indeed doubtful whether the modern usage arises from nature (d.s.).

Macbeth calls the witches’ prophesying a ‘supernatural soliciting’ (I, iii, 130). Witchcraft and magic are at first supernatural, I think, in a sense close to the theological. By the aid of spirits the magician does that which his own nature could not have done, or makes other objects do to each other what their natures were not capable of. It is not the spirits by whose aid he works that are supernatural but the operations performed. Again, when a prophet sees angels his experience is supernatural, in the sense already explained. It is equally so when he foresees the future. To call the angels themselves supernatural is, at first sight, no less odd than if we called the future supernatural. But certainly modern usage allows us to speak of ‘supernatural beings’. It is a usage philosophically scandalous. If demons and fairies do not exist, it is not clear why they should be called supernatural any more than the books that no one ever wrote. If they exist, no doubt they have their own natures and act according to them.

Several causes probably contributed to this sense. Whatever such creatures might be in themselves, our encounters with them are certainly not natural in the sense of being ordinary or ‘things of course’. It may even be supposed that when we see them we are acting above our nature. If on these two grounds the experience were vaguely felt to be supernatural, the adjective might then 67 be transferred to the things experienced. (It is of course linguistically irrelevant whether the experience is regarded as veridical or hallucinatory.) Again, such creatures are not part of the subject matter of ‘natural philosophy’; if real, they fall under pneumatology, and, if unreal, under morbid psychology. Thus the methodological idiom can separate them from nature. But thirdly (and I suspect this might be most potent of all), the beings which popular speech calls supernatural, long before that adjective was applied to them, were already bound together in popular thought by a common emotion. Some of them are holy, some numinous, some eerie, some horrible; all, one way or another, uncanny, mysterious, odd, ‘rum’. When the learned term supernatural enters the common speech, it finds this far older, emotional classification ready for it, and already in want of a name. I think the learned word, on the strength of a very superficial relation of meaning to the thing the plain man had in mind, was simply snatched at and pummelled into the required semantic shape, like an old hat. Just so the people have snatched at once learned words like sadist, inferiority-complex, romantic, or exotic, and forced them into the meanings they chose.

The process is apt to shock highly educated people, but it does not always serve the ends of language (communication) so ill as we might expect. Supernatural in this modern and, if you like, degraded sense, does its work quite efficiently. Anthropologists find it convenient to talk of ‘supernatural beings’ and everyone understands them; and if our friend says, ‘I can’t stand stories about the supernatural’, we know, for all ordinary purposes, what books 68 not to lend him. A general term whose particulars are bound together only by an emotion may be quite a practicable word provided that the emotion is well known and tolerably distinct.

4. Finally we have once (in Golding) ‘the supernaturalls of Aristotle’, meaning his Metaphysics. That leads to my next.

XIII. PHYSICAL AND METAPHYSICAL

Aristotle’s works were usually arranged in the following order: 1. The Organon (tool) or works on logic. 2. The scientific works or phusika. 3. A book or books on God, Unity, Being, Cause, and Potentiality. 4. Works on human activities (Ethics, Politics, Rhetoric, Poetics). As it was not very easy to find a name for the things in the third section, they were named simply from their position and called ‘the things after the phusika’ (ta meta ta phusika). When these ‘things’ came (no doubt wrongly) to be regarded as one book, this book was called ‘the Metaphysics’.

It would be easy to make an ironic point by saying that the word metaphysical, for all its grandiose suggestions, thus has no higher origin than a librarian’s practical device for indicating a subdivision of the Aristotelian corpus which nobody could find a name for. But the name is not so unhappy and certainly not so foreign to Aristotle’s thought as this sally would suggest. We have already seen that he believed in realities outside what he called phusis and made them the subject of disciplines distinct from phusike (or natural philosophy). If the names are superficial, the division they express is genuinely Aristotelian.

69

These names, and the academic arrangements which go with them, affect the semantic situation. Originally a thing was phusikon because you thought it belonged to, or was included in, phusis; your own definition of phusis would come into play. But once phusike (natural philosophy) as a subject, distinct from mathematike and metaphusike, exists, most people have a shorter way of deciding what is or is not phusikon. Any thing is phusikon if you meet it while doing your course in phusike. You need not ask what phusis itself is; you need only know whose lectures a thing comes in, in what year you read about it, finally for what examination it prepares you. Here, in fact, we have the Methodological Idiom at work.

Aristotle’s division of studies, or divisions derived from it, lasted for centuries. Under it a man who is phusikos means, not a ‘natural’ man but that particular kind of learned man who studies phusike. ‘Savants (philosophi)’, says Isidore, ‘are either physici or ethici or logici.’[96] The physici study natures—sort things out and tell you their kinds. But the part of their work which the public is most interested in is, of course, that which may relieve our pains or preserve our life. Hence the physicus or physician comes to mean primarily a doctor of medicine. The stuff he gives you becomes physic (‘throw physic to the dogs’, says Macbeth, V, iii, 47). The adjective physical comes to mean medicinal, or ‘good for you’; so that Portia can say

Is Brutus sick, and is it physical

To walk unbraced and suck up the humours

Of the dank morning?[97]

70

Metaphysical, as we should expect, comes to mean (in the popular sense) supernatural; either as ‘pertaining to what things do when acting beyond their natures’, or (more probably) ‘studied by arts and sciences which go beyond those of the physicus’. Hence in Marlowe a magical ointment has been ‘tempered by science metaphisicall’;[98] and witchcraft is for Lady Macbeth ‘metaphysical aid’ (I, v, 30).

Phusike (natural philosophy) had from its beginning been ‘principally concerned with bodies’, as Aristotle notes.[99] It was therefore to be expected that physical, by the methodological idiom, would sooner or later come to its modern sense of ‘corporeal’. This tendency would be encouraged by the fact that, as special sciences which dealt with bodies from a special point of view (like chemistry) or with only some bodies (like botany) were quarried out of the once undifferentiated phusike, and were given their separate names, phusike, left like a sort of rump, became the name of that science which still dealt with bodies, or matter, as such. The plural form physics survives to remind us that it was once all ‘the phusika’, as metaphysics were once ‘the things after the phusika’. A singular form, metaphysic, is now gaining ground, but physics will perhaps hardly drop its final -s until the meaning ‘medicine’ for the word physic has become more completely archaic.

‘Corporeal’ is a mildly dangerous sense of physical. When Baxter says ‘common love to God and special saving love to God be both acts upon an object physically 71 the same’,[100] physically means ‘in its own nature’. When Hooker says that sacraments ‘are not physical but moral instruments of salvation’ (V, lvii, 4) I do not think he means ‘corporeal’ by physical any more than ‘ethical’ by ‘moral’. He probably means ‘Their efficacy is of the sort that would be studied by moral, not by natural, philosophy’.

XIV. THE ‘NATURAL’ AS THE EXCUSABLE

Coleridge once entitled a piece of verse ‘Something childish but very natural’. In Rider Haggard’s She, when the young native unwisely avows her passion for Leo in the presence of the Queen, Holly pleads ‘Be pitiful . . . it is but Nature working’ (ch. XVIII). ‘It’s only natural’ is used daily in the same deprecatory way. One extenuates one’s peccadillo as natural, I suspect, in more than one sense. It is natural, ordinary, a thing in the common course, I’m no worse than others. It is at least not unnatural, I have been foolish or faulty at least in human, not in bestial or diabolical, fashion. What I did was natural, spontaneous, I have not gone out of my way to invent new vices. Sometimes a higher plea, less of a defence than a counter-attack, is urged, as in Pope’s

Can sins of moment(s) claim the rod

Of everlasting fires,

And that offend great Nature’s God

Which Nature’s self inspires?[101]

A medieval poet would have been surprised to find Great Mother Nature inspiring sins, for he would have supposed that her ‘inspiration’, so far as concerned man, lay in 72 the nature (animal rationale) appointed by her for man. Pope is closer to Dryden’s Abdalla; the ‘voice’ of Nature here is the less rational, less specifically human, element in us.

XV. ‘NATURE’ IN EIGHTEENTH- AND NINETEENTH-CENTURY POETRY

Nature (d.s.) and hardly even demoted, appears in Pope’s couplet

All are but parts of one stupendous whole

Whose body Nature is and God the soul.[102]

When Thomson, on the other hand, describes the colour green as ‘Nature’s universal robe’[103] an enormous shrinkage has occurred. Most of nature (d.s.), as anyone can see on a fine night, is not green but black, and the better the visibility the blacker. Even terrestrial nature is by no means all green. Thomson is actually thinking of British landscapes when he says Nature.

Wordsworth’s doctrine of Nature does not here concern us; his contrasts make it clear how he (and others, and presently thousands of others) used the word. In the Prelude Coleridge is congratulated on the fact that, though ‘reared in the great city’, he had ‘long desired to serve in Nature’s temple’ (II, 452-63). Nature, in fact, or anyway her ‘temple’, excludes towns. ‘Science’ and ‘arts’ are contrasted with Nature in III, 371-78; books and Nature in V, 166-73; Man and Nature in IV, 352, and of course in the sub-title of Book VIII. Whatever his doctrine may have been, he does not in fact use nature in the d.s.; for nature (d.s.) of course includes towns, arts, sciences, books, and 73 men. The antithesis of Nature and man, and again of nature and the man-made, underlie his usages, and those of most ‘nature poets’.

For most purposes, then, Nature in them means the country as opposed to the town, though it may in particular passages be extended to cover the sun, moon, and stars. It may also, despite its frequent opposition to ‘man’, sometimes cover the rustic way of (human) life. It is the country conceived as something not ‘man-made’; Cowper’s (or Varro’s)[104] maxim that God made the country and man made the town is always more or less present. That the landscape in most civilised countries is through and through modified by human skill and toil, or that the effect of most ‘town-scapes’ is enormously indebted to atmospheric conditions, is overlooked.

This does not at all mean that the poets are talking nonsense. They are expressing a way of looking at things which must arise when towns become very large and the urban way of life very different from the rural. When this happens most people (not all) feel a sense of relief and restoration on getting out into the country; it is a serious emotion and a recurrent one, a proper theme for high poetry. Philosophically, no doubt, it is superficial to say we have escaped from the works of man to those of Nature when in fact, smoking a man-made pipe and swinging a man-made stick, wearing our man-made boots and clothes, we pause on a man-made bridge to 74 look down on the banked, narrowed, and deepened river which man has made out of the original wide, shallow, and swampy mess, and across it, at a landscape which has only its larger geological features in common with that which would have existed if man had never interfered. But we are expressing something we really feel. The wider range of vision has something to do with it; we are seeing more of nature (in a good many senses) than we could in a street. Again, the natural forces which keep the buildings of a town together (all the stresses) are only inferred; the natural action of weather and vegetation is visible. And there are fewer men about; therefore, by one of our habitual contrasts, more nature. We also feel (most of us) that we are, for the moment, in conditions more suited to our own nature—to our lungs, nostrils, ears and eyes.

But I need not labour the point. Romantic nature, like the popular use of supernatural, is not an idle term because it seems at first to stand up badly to logical criticism. People know pretty well what they mean by it and sometimes use it to communicate what would not easily be communicable in other ways. To be sure, they may also use it to say vaguely and flatly (or even ridiculously) what might have been said precisely and freshly if they had had no such tool ready. I once saw a railway poster which advertised Kent as ‘Nature’s home’; and we have all heard of the lady who liked walking on a road ‘untouched by the hand of man’.

75

3
SAD
[WITH GRAVIS]

I. ‘GRAVIS’ AND ‘GRAVE’

Though sad has never, to my knowledge, been influenced by Latin gravis and its English derivative grave, the likeness between their semantic histories makes it natural to begin this chapter with a glance at the latter.

As everyone knows gravis means ‘heavy’. And because we do not like carrying or ‘bearing’ heavy objects, it also means ‘grievous’. O passi graviora, says Aeneas, oh you who have suffered worse things than this![105] English heavy more often than English grave corresponds to this sense; as in Spenser’s ‘O heavie herse!’[106] It is true that we speak of ’grave danger’ or ‘a grave disaster’, but this, I believe, brings in something of the next sense.

What is heavy is, in all physical operations, important. We cannot put it where we want it without effort, perhaps not even without planning; and, in return, wind or water or enemies cannot easily remove it. It will ‘stay put’. It is, every way, something serious, something to be reckoned with. Gravis therefore also describes the sort of man who has to be reckoned with; the man whose action or opinion, as we significantly say, ‘carries weight’. (Memories of muscular exertion turn up at every moment 76 in this semantic area.) Lucretius, depreciating Heraclitus, says he has a higher reputation among those Greeks who are inanes than among those Greeks who are gravis and really want to know the truth. The contrast is between ‘empty’ and ‘heavy’ Greeks (an empty jug is lighter than a full one); between dilettanti or frivolous ones who make philosophy a hobby and those who are in earnest, serious—solides as the French say. This merges into the sense ‘venerable, authoritative, or august’. Thus in Virgil: ‘if the crowd catches sight of a man who is gravis by reason of his pietas and his good record’.[107]

This sense is pretty accurately reproduced by the English word when Othello says ‘Most potent, grave, and reverend Seniors’ (I, iii, 76) or Ariel salutes Prospero as ’grave Sir’ (I, ii, 189). We are moving a little away from it when Milton says ‘the men, though grave, eyed them’.[108] Grave here probably means something like ‘serious-minded’ with a more specifically religious and moral emphasis than the Lucretian, Virgilian, and Shakespearian uses would bear. And perhaps it already includes some reference to the externals of mien and deportment. It was certainly in this latter and more external sense that the word developed. Gulliver says the Brobdingnagian clothes ‘are a very grave and decent habit’ (ch. III). And everyone will remember the parish bull who was in reality ‘no way equal to the department’ but of whom Mr Shandy had a ‘high opinion’ because ‘he went through the business with a grave face’.[109]

77

II. ‘SAD’: THE ‘FULL’-SENSES

Anglo-Saxon sæd (plural sade) is brother to Old Norse saddr and cousin to Latin satur, and all three words have originally the same meaning: gorged, full (of food), replete. Thus in Psalm lxxviii. 30, where the Latin has manducaverunt et saturati sunt nimis, and Coverdale ‘So they did eat and were well-filled’, an Anglo-Saxon translator has ‘They ate largely (swiþe) and became sade’. In Old Norse saddr lifdaga ‘full of life-days’ is equivalent to the biblical ‘full of years’.

The distinction between having had enough and having had too much is, as we all know, a fine one. Our modern ‘fed up’ bears witness to it; also, though here litotes comes into it, the common use of ‘I’ve had enough of your impudence’ to mean ‘I have had more than I want’. And to say of a man who wants to stop fighting ‘He’s had his bellyful’, though a trifle archaic, would still be an intelligible taunt. Saddr and sæd both underwent this development. In the Laxdale Saga the cowman, flying from Hrapp’s ghost (which he has met several times before) says ‘I am saddr of wrestling with him’ (ch. XXIV). ‘I’m fed up with’ or ‘I’ve had enough of’ would be equally accurate translations. A somewhat similar use occurs in Anglo-Saxon poetry. The Brunnanburh poem says of the battlefield ‘there lay many a man, weary and sæd of war’—many a man who ‘had his fill’ of it in the sense that he was dead or dying.[110] There is no taunt here; only the wry and grim pity 78 of the Old Germanic style. Wiglaf dashed water over Beowulf who was ‘sæd of battle’, i.e. mortally wounded (l. 2722).

The sense ‘over-full’ or ‘fed up’ descended into Middle English. In the Owl and Nightingale the latter says that she does not sing all the year round because she does not want her audience to become to sade, too satiated (l. 452). Chaucer observes that inveterate alchemists can never ‘wexen sadde’, never grow tired of their delusive art (G. 877).

It is tempting to derive the modern sense of ‘melancholy’ (sad (d.s.)) directly and exclusively from the sense ‘fed up’, but this would be rash.

Now a man—or a thing—that is full is heavier than one that is empty. ‘Heavy’ therefore becomes one of the meanings of sæd. Gower says that the Earth ‘is schape round, Substantial, strong, sad and sound’ (VII, 225). So in Cotgrave’s French Dictionary (1611) we find Fromage de taulpe defined as ‘heavy or sad cheese’; and in many parts of the country till this day we call ‘sad’ a cake or loaf which has not risen. Where the English version of the Romance of the Rose speaks of ‘sadde burdens’ that make men’s shoulders ache, one who did not know the history of the word would see a psychological epithet; in reality, sadde means just ‘heavy’.[111]

Emptiness and hollowness, fulness and solidity, are closely related conceptions. We need therefore feel no surprise to find Wycliff saying ‘the altar was not sad but hollow’.[112] But this opens the way to a much more important 79 development. Sad becomes the equivalent of Latin solidus and, whether as the result of this equivalence or not, takes on many of the same meanings: firm (the opposite of flimsy), complete (not broken or interrupted), reliable, sound. Virgil describes the spear to which her father bound the infant Camilla as solidum;[113] Gavin Douglas renders it ‘the schaft was sad and sound’—a collocation of adjectives we had in Gower a moment ago. In Malory sadly is used where we should use soundly: ‘and there he found a bed and laid him therein and fell on sleep sadly’[114]—fell sound asleep. And when Chaucer says ‘The messenger drank sadly ale and wyn’ (B. 743) we could almost translate it ‘drank solidly’—settled down, as the sequel shows (for he was soon ‘sleeping like a pig’), to a solid, or uninterrupted, or sound, or heavy, or serious, evening’s toping.

III. THE ‘GRAVE’-SENSES

When sad has acquired the meaning ‘firm’ or ‘sound’ it will almost inevitably be applied to human character. Thus the person who ‘like seasoned timber never gives’ will be sad. We find the word applied to a good wife: ‘o dere wyf . . . that were to me so sad and eek so trewe’.[115] Sadness is the proper virtue of mature or elderly people. Lydgate bids us ‘In youth be lusty, sad when thou art olde’.[116] The virtue of sadness is hardly to be expected in youth, but sometimes we are pleasantly surprised to find 80 an old head on young shoulders. Thus we are told of Griselda

though this mayde tendre wer of age,

Yet in the brest of hir virginitie

Ther was enclosed rype and sad corage.[117]

In the same tale the fickle rabble run with enthusiasm to welcome Walter’s new wife because they are ‘unsad and ever untrewe’ (l. 995), unstable and faithless. The ‘sadde folk’ (l. 1002) who censure this new-fangleness are what a Roman would have called graviores; men of principle, not to be blown about by every gust of fashion.

It will be noticed—so deeply is thought in debt to the senses—that in all these instances sad has still so much attachment to the idea of weight, that the adjective ‘light’ could be its opposite. It returns also to the physical level by another route. Bodily acts, if firm and steady, can be sad: ‘in goon the speres ful sadly in arest’.[118] They are firmly laid in the rest, in a manner which shows that the combatants mean business. And of course a face will be sad when its expression betokens sadness within. The narrator in Pearl had last seen his daughter as an infant; by a contrast of immense poetical power she comes before him in the trans-mortal country with ‘semblant sad for doc other erle’ (l. 211), with all the state and gravity of a great nobleman. So, later in the poem, the Elders before the Throne are ‘sad of chere’ (l. 887).

In both these passages any intrusion of sad (d.s.) (melancholy, dejected) would be ruinous. But in the Clerk’s Tale (E. 693) it would make sheer nonsense. We 81 are told that if Walter had not known, on other grounds, how dearly Griselda loved her children, he would have thought her cruel for wearing such a ‘sad visage’ when she submitted to the murder of her son. Sad here is, of course, composed, unmoved, the opposite of distraught. It is indeed used as a translation of compositus in Chaucer’s Boethius.[119] Her heart was breaking but her face did not show it. This is perhaps the strongest instance I know of the context’s insulating power. For that very sense of sad which would have made the passage idiotic already existed in Chaucer’s time. Obviously, he has not the slightest fear that anyone will thrust it in at this point.

IV. ‘SAD (D.S.)’

The evidence of its existence comes in Chaucer himself. In his version of the Romance of the Rose (l. 211) he says of Avarice, ‘full sad . . . was she’, where Guillaume de Lorris had maigre (199. Var. laide). We may not think sad (d.s.) a very good translation of either, but all the other senses of sad are impossible. He cannot be calling Avarice full-fed, or heavy, or reliable, or composed. He must mean ‘gloomy’, ‘miserable’. But it is not easy, in the fourteenth century, to find any other unambiguous example. The N.E.D. finds one in another Chaucerian passage, where Theseus ‘with a sad visage . . . syked stille’ (A. 2985). But the dangerous sense seems to me here to be at best only possible. In the whole passage Theseus is giving an exhibition of gravitas. He has sent for Palamon and Emelye. He waits till they are seated and till the presence 82 chamber is silent. He then remains silent himself for a while and—admirable touch—‘his eyen sette he ther as was his lest’ (l. 2983), fixed his eyes on what he chose. He sighed stille, quietly, and proceeded to make a high philosophical speech beginning with the First Mover. I cannot feel sure that the sad visage was—and I feel quite sure it need not have been—anything more than a grave, a staid, a composed, and an authoritative countenance. He is being compositus, gravis. More promising is the Lyric 105 in Carleton Brown’s Religious Lyrics of the Fourteenth Century, where the second line reads ‘For sorowe sore I sykkit sadde’. Here the dangerous sense seems to me the most probable. But it is not certain. The mourner may have sighed sadly as Chaucer’s messenger drank sadly: continuously, steadily, ‘in a big way’.

By the later sixteenth century, sad (d.s.), though not in exclusive possession, is common—‘in sad cypress let me be laid’, ‘tell sad stories of the death of kings’, ‘sad Celeno’ singing a song ‘that hart of flint asonder could have rifte’.[120]

As often, we have no difficulty in suggesting ways in which the word could have arrived at this sense. Rather, the possible ways are so numerous that we cannot hope to determine which counted for most.

From the very nature of metaphor a word that means ‘heavy’ will be very likely to acquire the meaning ‘grievous’. A word that means ‘fed up’ will be very likely to acquire the meaning ‘displeased, ill-content’. A word which means ’grave’ or even ‘steady-going’ will 83 necessarily mean the opposite of ‘light’ or ‘sportive’. Thus we find sad used to mean ‘serious’, i.e. not joking. ‘Speak you this with a sad brow?’, are you in earnest?[121] And what is serious will always be thought gloomy by some, and gloom may by litotes be called seriousness. Pensive, from meaning ‘thoughtful’, came to mean ‘melancholy’ by some such process. Again, what is sad in the sense of firm or thoroughgoing or earnest will in some contexts refer to what is also grievous. When Malory wrote ‘They drew their swords and gave many sad strokes’ (VII, 8), did he mean earnest, all-out strokes (they did not ‘pull their punches’), or grim and grievous strokes? Perhaps he could not have told us.

Almost every sense the word ever bore might have had some share in producing sad (d.s.).

V. OUR POLLY IS A ‘SAD’ SLUT

So runs the song in The Beggars’ Opera. We may put beside it, from Farquhar’s Recruiting Officer (III, ii), ‘An ignorant, pretending, impudent coxcomb—Aye, aye, a sad dog’ and ‘He’s a Whig, Sir, a sad dog’,[122] and finally Mary Crawford’s address to Fanny, ‘Sad, sad girl: I do not know when I shall have done scolding you’.[123] I am in great doubt how these arose.

They might owe something to the same sort of transference which has given two meanings to the words sorry and wretch. In logic one who is sorry (Anglo-Saxon sarig) ought to be one who is sore, in pain, miserable. But it can 84 also be one who is vile and unsatisfactory—‘a sorry knave’; whence also a sorry inn, a sorry nag, or ‘sorry cheer’ (a bad meal). A wretch (Anglo-Saxon wrecca) ought to be an exile, hence (significantly—there is much Volkwanderung in the background) in Anglo-Saxon poetry a hero, but soon a ‘down and out’, a miserable outcast. But a wretch can also be a vile person, a villain. ‘Princes have been sold by wretches to whose care they were entrusted’, says Johnson.[124] Thus the sorry man may be not the one who is himself dissatisfied but the one who causes our dissatisfaction; the wretch far from feeling wretchedness, may inflict it on others. Possibly in the same way sad may be transferred to the person who makes us sad, in whichever sense; either makes us ‘fed up’ (we have soon had quite enough of him), or makes us serious, or makes us melancholy.

But I fancy there is another possibility. Chaucer’s messenger drank sadly; that is thoroughly, or seriously—‘meant business’. The spears went sadly in the rest because they also meant business. A sad instance of anything undesirable could be a serious instance of it. Do Polly’s parents, when they call her ‘a sad slut’ mean that she is a serious, weighty, important instance of sluttery—is among sluts what ‘a grave disaster’ is among disasters? Are the ‘sad dogs’ advanced or grave cases of doggery? If so, Mary Crawford’s ‘sad girl’ would be in a separate category. The previous examples have in view a species which is undesirable as a whole (sluts, dogs) and mark out one person as a prime specimen of it. But Mary Crawford of course did not think girls an undesirable species. Her 85 usage would show sad in this sense going on after the original shade of meaning has been forgotten.

While both are conjectural I cannot help thinking the second process the more likely. The passages where sad is used in this way usually have, to my ear, some hint of the humorous about them; never the downright, wholehearted condemnation of the word wretch. This seems to me to fit better with the idea of the ‘prime specimen’.

86

4
WIT
[WITH INGENIUM]

If a man had time to study the history of one word only, wit would perhaps be the best word he could choose. Its fortunes provide almost perfect examples of the main principles at work in semantic development. Its early life was happy and free from complications. It then acquired a sense which brought into full play the distinction between the word’s and the speaker’s meanings. It also suffered the worst fate any word has to fear; it became the fashionable term of approval among critics. This made it a prey to tactical definitions of a more than usually unscrupulous type, and in the heat of controversy there was some danger of its becoming a mere rallying-cry, semantically null. Meanwhile, however, popular usage was irresistibly at work in a different direction; in the end those ‘who speak only to be understood’ rescued it from the critics and fixed upon it the useful meaning it bears to-day. The chequered story has—what is rare in such matters—a happy ending.

I. EARLY HISTORY

Anglo-Saxon wit or gewit is mind, reason, intelligence. Rational creatures are those to whom God has given wit.[125] A mortally wounded man, until delirium or unconsciousness 87 overtakes him, still is master of his gewitt.[126] And of course these, or closely similar, senses survived for centuries. When a man is mad his ‘wit’s diseased’.[127] As he grows older his wit ‘ought to be more’, he ought to have more sense.[128] Davies (anticipating Paradise Lost VIII, 76f.) says that God left some problems dark ‘to punish pride of wit’, the pride of man’s intellect,[129] and Pope follows him with the saw that Nature ‘wisely curbed proved man’s pretending wit’.[130] In Ireland, and perhaps elsewhere, we still say ‘God give you wit’ or ‘If you’d only had the wit to get his address’, meaning by wit sense or gumption. In all such usages the ancient meaning is insulated from the contamination of later meanings by the context. And the context can have this insulating power even if it is only a single clause:

for a calm unfit,

Would steer too nigh the sands to boast his wit.

Great wits are sure to madness near allied.[131]

The first wit means ‘sense’, common sense, prudence. But wits in the next line means a good deal more. The full stop, the adjective great, and the fact that the whole line is a traditional maxim, lead the reader, and perhaps led Dryden, to make the adjustment unconsciously.

II. WITS

Two quite different causes lead to the frequent use of wits in the plural. One is the old psychology with its five 88 inward and five outward wits or senses.[132] In Benedick’s encounter with Beatrice ‘four of his five wits went halting off’.[133] This usage, so far as I can see, had almost no effect on other senses of the word.

The second cause is far more interesting. Men differ from one another not only in the amount of wit or intelligence they have but in the kind. Each man’s wit has its own cast, bent, or temper; one quick and another plodding, one solid and another showy, one ingenious to invent and another accurate to retain. Thus as we speak of sceptical or credulous, creative or analytic, ‘minds’, you could once speak of wits to mean types of mind, or ‘mentalities’, or the people who have them. Thus in Chaucer

For tendre wittes wenen al be wyle

Theras they can nat pleynly understande[134]

people of ‘tender’ mind. The classic place for this usage is the account of ‘quick’ and ‘hard’ wits in Ascham’s Scholemaster.

This sense of wit, unimportant though it may seem at the first glance, actually opened the way to nearly all the later developments. Without this sense wit is something common to all rational creatures or at least to all men of good sense. But a man’s wit in this sense is something which can distinguish him, which is characteristic of him; his mental make-up.

One obvious result of this is to make wit the recognised translation of ingenium. Whether its constant use for that purpose actually helped to mould its meaning, or merely 89 allows us to see more clearly just what that meaning was, I do not know. But a study of wit which does not take full account of its relation to ingenium would be out of court; and a full study, which I do not attempt, would have to spend some time on the Italian ingegno as well.

III. ‘INGENIUM’

This word, like natura in its earlier use, originally meant the character or ‘what-sortedness’ of a thing, so that Tacitus can talk about the ingenium of a hill.[135] It concerns us, however, only when it is applied, as it far more often is, to human beings. ‘Precepts’, says Seneca, ‘lead to right actions only if they meet a pliant ingenium.’[136] Here ‘nature’ or ‘character’ would do. Elsewhere the word refers specifically to a man’s intellectual quality. Epicurus, says Lucretius, surpassed the whole human race in ingenium (III, 1043). Helvidius, in Tacitus, had at an early age turned his brilliant ingenium to the study of philosophy.[137] The same tendency which has made ‘family’ mean good family, and ‘quality’ good quality, brought it about that ingenium should usually mean not merely ‘cast of mind’ but a ‘cast of mind above the ordinary’. Quintilian quotes from Cicero ‘Whatever my share of ingenium, which I know to be small, may be’ and ‘What I lack in ingenium I make up for by hard work’ (XI, i). The word obviously means something like cleverness, ability, high intellectual capacity. ‘Quickness to learn and memory . . . are summed up in the single word ingenium’, says Cicero,[138] 90 and adds that those who have them are called ingeniosi. But he includes too little, and it is indeed possible on other grounds that some words have dropped out of the text. Ingenium really means something more like ‘talent’ or even ‘genius’. This is clear when it is used in the plural to mean ‘men who have ingenium’ (we also speak about ‘men of talent’ as ‘talents’). When Tacitus says that the reign of Augustus has not lacked for its historians decora ingenia,[139] we can hardly translate this by anything weaker than ‘distinguished talents’. So, when Suetonius records that Vespasian ‘patronised ingenia and the arts’,[140] we must say ‘patronised genius’ or ‘talent’ (i.e. men of talent).

IV. ‘INGENIUM’ AND WIT

The liaison, so to call it, between these two words is much closer than I realised before I looked into the matter.

The one is the almost invariable translation of the other. Ingenii gloriam in Boethius[141] becomes ‘glory of wit’ in J.T.’s version (1609). The Lucretian vaunt that Epicurus surpassed all mankind in ingenium, which I quoted a minute ago, is rendered by Burton ‘Whose wit excelled the wits of men so far’.[142] Horace writes

Ingeniis non ille favet plauditque sepultis

Nostra sed impugnat,[143]

literally ‘He does not favour and applaud buried ingenia but attacks our own’. Dryden translates it ‘He favours not dead wits but hates the living’.[144] Shakespeare, when 91 he speaks about ‘the wits of former days’ (Sonnet LIX) means exactly the same; the writers of talent or genius who flourished before his own time.

But wit does not appear only as the translation of ingenium; both words enter into exactly the same traditional antitheses.

Nullum magnum ingenium sine mixtura dementiae, no great ingenium without a dash of insanity, from Seneca’s De Tranquillitate (XVII, 4), becomes Dryden’s ‘Great wits are sure to madness near allied’.

‘You get what is called affectation (kakozelon) when ingenium lacks judicium.’[145] ‘It is a bad sign when a boy’s judicium gets ahead of his ingenium.’[146]. This contrasted pair will be familiar to all readers of neo-classical criticism. Harvey, in Cowley’s Ode (stanza 13), has ‘so strong a wit as all things but his Judgment overcame’. ‘Wit and Judgment often are at strife,’ says Pope.[147]

‘The poem of Lucretius has many flashes of ingenium, but also much art.’[148] Pope makes the same dichotomy when he speaks of a work where ‘Wit and Art conspire to move your mind’.[149]

An author may be too fond of his own ingenium, nimium amator ingenii sui.[150] Pope reproduces both this idea and also the antithesis of ingenium and judicium in one couplet:

Authors are partial to their wit, ’tis true.

But are not critics to their judgment too.[151]

92

The difficulty here is to find, for our own purpose, a word to express what ingenium and wit both clearly mean. One cannot call it either ‘talent’ or ‘genius’ without foisting upon the Roman and English writers a far later, and Romantic, distinction; and ‘genius’ labours further under the disadvantage of having no tolerable plural. But what is hard to express is easy to understand. What is being talked about is the thing which, in its highest exaltation may border on madness; the productive, seminal (modern cant would say ‘creative’) thing, as distinct from the critical faculty of judicium; the thing supplied by nature, not acquired by skill (ars); the thing which he who has it may love too well and follow intemperately. It is what distinguishes the great writer and especially the great poet. It is therefore very close to ‘imagination’. Indeed, there is one Latin passage where ingenium can hardly be translated except by that very word. It comes at the beginning of Cicero’s De Legibus. Atticus looks round to see the oak which had been mentioned in Cicero’s poem Marius and asks if it is still alive. ‘Yes,’ comes the answer, ‘it is, and always will be, for it was planted by ingenium.’ It was an imaginary tree (I, i).

Since English words fail us, and since we may now bid goodbye to Latin itself, for the rest of this chapter I am going to call the sense of the word wit which we have been observing ‘the ingenium sense’ or ‘wit-ingenium’. And it seems to me absolutely essential to face this sense squarely and get it firmly fixed in our minds. If we once allow more familiar, though not necessarily later, meanings 93 to colour our reading of the word wit wherever the neo-classical writers use it, we shall get into hopeless confusion.

This error has, I believe, been committed by a critic to whose ingenium we all owe a willing debt. In his Structure of Complex Words (p. 87) Professor Empson, speaking of the word wit in Pope’s Essay on Criticism, says that ‘there is not a single use of the word in the whole poem in which the idea of a joke is quite out of sight. Indeed I think that the whole structure of thought in the poem depends on this.’ Now I think there are plenty of passages where it is simply wit-ingenium with no idea of a joke, however far in the background. ‘Great Wits may sometimes gloriously offend’ (I, 152). Surely it is the great ingenia who are thus entitled to dispense with rule (l. 144) and transcend art (l. 154)? It is an affair of ‘nameless graces’ (l. 144) attainable only by a ‘master-hand’ (l. 145); a privilege best reserved for the ancients (l. 161) who have something like a royal prerogative (l. 162). The result pleases, but pleases like ‘the shapeless rock, or hanging precipice’ (l. 160) which Pope certainly did not find jocular. The truth seems to me to be that he is here handling what is almost a locus communis. Democritus, quoted by Horace, had said that ingenium was happier than ‘painful’ or ‘beggarly’ (misera) art.[152] Milton, probably with that very word misera in mind, confesses that Shakespeare’s ‘easy numbers’ flow ‘to the shame of slow endeavouring art’. Closest to Pope is Boileau’s

par quel transport heureux

Quelquefois dans sa course un esprit vigoureux,

94

Trop resserré par l’art, sort des règles prescrites,

Et de l’art mesme apprend à franchir leurs limites.[153]

None of these provides a background which makes Professor Empson’s view probable. And what of the ‘patriarch wits’ who survived a thousand years (II, 479)? Does this mean only Aristophanes and Lucian? I think rather, Homer, Sophocles, and Virgil.

But the crucial experiment is still to try. No interpretation of the word wit is acceptable unless it can stand up to the couplet

Some have at first for wits, then poets passed,

Turn’d critics next, and proved plain fools at last.[154]

Clearly the whole rhetorical structure is in ruins unless we can find senses for the key-words which provide a continuous descent; a poet must be something inferior to a wit, a critic to a poet, and a ‘plain fool’ to a critic.

Unfortunately the word poet, as well as wit, now needs explanation. Poet has in our time become a term of laudation rather than of description, so that to speak of a ‘bad poet’ is for some almost an oxymoron. Dr Leavis, if I remember rightly, wrote to a paper to say that Mr Auden was not a poet. But of course there is another sense in which everyone, including Dr Leavis, would have to classify Mr Auden as a poet; the sense any teacher would be using if he said ‘No, no. You’re confusing Lucan and Lucian. The one was a Latin poet; the other a Greek prose-writer.’ The seventeenth- and eighteenth-century usage, if not identical with the teacher’s, was far nearer to 95 his than to Dr Leavis’s. Johnson, who defines poetry as ‘metrical composition’, defines poet as ‘An inventor; an author of fiction; a writer of poems; one who writes in measure’. We can gauge how far we have travelled[155] by comparing this with the Shorter Oxford Dictionary which, after a definition very like Johnson’s, feels obliged to add ‘A writer in verse (or sometimes in elevated prose) distinguished by imaginative power, insight, sensibility, and faculty of expression’. Johnson is probably pretty true to the age immediately before his own. Fiction and metre were the chief differentiae of the ‘poet’. Thus Shadwell is a poet in the Epilogue to The Silent Lovers (l. 9) and ‘our poet’ in that to The Squire of Alsatia. Even when he wrote verse, to call a man a poet implied neither that he had, nor that he had not, what we now call ‘poetic genius’. It was parallel to calling him an architect or an actor. It told you what craft or profession he followed; like calling him ‘an author’.

With this proviso, does not Pope’s couplet become plain when—but only when—we take wit as wit-ingenium? ‘Some have at first passed for men of genius; then for authors (or literary craftsmen); then for critics; and finally have proved fools.’

In the light of this two Drydenian passages are ‘patient’ (as the old divines said) of a far more important interpretation than they have usually received. In the Essay of Dramatic Poesy we are told that Jonson was ‘the more 96 correct poet, but Shakespeare the greater wit’.[156] In the Original and Progress of Satire it is said ‘if we are not so great wits as Donne, yet certainly we are better poets’.[157] I believe the meaning of both to be almost the opposite of that which naturally occurs first to a modern reader. Wit and wits are used in the ingenium-sense. Dryden is saying that while Jonson was the more disciplined craftsman, Shakespeare was the greater genius; that while we have less genius than Donne we have more literary skill. This is borne out by the fact that he has just censured Donne for insufficient care for ‘words’ and ‘numbers’. In a word, Dryden is almost (not quite) saying that Shakespeare is, in one sense, a greater poet than Jonson; and Donne, in one sense, a greater poet than himself and his contemporaries.

It must be understood that the error of which I venture to suspect Professor Empson is not one in chronology. That sense of the word wit which he feels delicately present throughout the Essay on Criticism certainly existed in Pope’s time, and long before. It was destined to destroy the ingenium-sense in the end. The question between Professor Empson and me is whether that slowly rising tide had yet reached all Pope’s uses of the word. I believe it had not; the insulating power of the context still protected them. We will now leave wit-ingenium in its lofty, yet already precarious, position, and say something of this other sense.

97

V. EARLY HISTORY OF THE ‘DANGEROUS SENSE’

I take it that wit in the sense now current means that sort of mental agility or gymnastic which uses language as the principal equipment of its gymnasium. ‘Language’ must here be taken in a large sense, to include those proverbs, and quotations almost equivalent to proverbs, which are among the ordinary small change of conversation. Thus the Frenchman’s comment on the Munich agreement (ce n’est pas magnifique, mais ce n’est pas la guerre) or Lady Dorothy Neville’s protest to the cook (‘you cannot serve cod and salmon’) are wit because the familiar gnomae which they appositely pervert make part of the whole linguistic situation in which they were said. Pun, half pun, assonance, epigram (in the modern sense) and distorted proverb or quotation are all witty. Hence of all the excellences prose can have it is the least translatable. This is the dangerous sense of wit and I shall refer to it henceforward as wit (d.s.). But besides wit (d.s.) and wit-ingenium we also need a name for the word’s earliest sense, for wit meaning mind, rationality, good sense. I call this wit (old sense).

There is no doubt that wit (d.s.) was current in the seventeenth century, but it is impossible to determine exactly when it arose. The reason for this impossibility is clear enough. A man’s intelligence (wit (old sense)) impresses other people most and is most talked about if he displays it in conversation. But no way of displaying it in conversation will be so obvious or so attractive to most hearers as repartee, epigram, and general dexterity—wit 98 (d.s.). The evidence on which men attribute wit (old sense) to anyone will therefore very often be the wit (d.s.) of his talk. When wit (d.s.) has fully established itself in the language a very careful speaker might make a distinction between the quality shown in conversation and the general calibre of mind inferred from it. But not one speaker in a thousand has any care for such things, and until the quality in question has a name the distinction cannot easily be put into words. Hence there will be a period during which such a remark as ‘My lord showed prodigious wit in his discourse to-day’ is ambiguous. Does it mean ‘The wit (d.s.) of what he said was prodigious’, or ‘What he said showed (proved) that he has a prodigious wit (old sense)’? The speaker will not know and will not have raised the question.

We are told that Benedick and Beatrice ‘never meet but there’s a skirmish of wit between them’.[158] No one doubts that what they displayed in fact was wit (d.s.). But is the speaker using the word in the dangerous sense, or does he only mean they set their brains at one another, skirmish with their wit (old sense)?

So with Falstaff’s ‘I am not only witty myself but the cause that wit is in other men’.[159] So long as wit had its Old Sense, witty of course meant wise; as it does, though mockingly, in Tamburlaine (I, iv, 686), ‘Are you the witty king of Persia?’ Is Falstaff calling himself wise? or spiritual? The wit displayed by the other men was, as the context shows, the ‘invention’ of things that ‘tend to laughter’. This too could be wit in more than one sense.

99

There is, once more, no doubt about the fact of Falstaff’s wit (d.s.), and little doubt that his wit (d.s.) is, in part anyway, the thing he is referring to, the ground on which he bases his claim to be witty. But this does not prove that wit in his language already has the dangerous sense.

We may clarify the situation from a parallel case where the two senses of a word admit different spellings. A lady may show her courtesy by making a curtsy; more briefly, may show her courtesy by her curtsy. The fact that someone then speaks of her courtesy on a particular occasion, when her courtesy was wholly contained in her curtsy (she said nothing, and did nothing except making a curtsy), would not prove that courtesy had for him the sense curtsy. It is our distinction between word’s meaning and speaker’s meaning. From one point of view the speaker means by ‘her courtesy’ nothing more or less or other than her curtsy. But that need not be the sense, nor even a sense, of courtesy in his language. So here. What the Shakespearian characters are referring to may be in fact wit (d.s.) so that this becomes the speaker’s meaning of the word at that moment. It need not yet be the word’s meaning.

But clearly it soon will be one of the word’s meanings. If that particular gesture we now call a curtsy becomes the obligatory method by which every lady shows her courtesy on entering a room—so that girls who forget it will be reprimanded by a mother’s or duenna’s sharp ‘Remember your courtesy’ (i.e. your good manners)—then, with or without change of spelling, a new sense of 100 courtesy in which it means simply this gesture, is almost bound to arise, and its very connection with cortesia in general may be forgotten. Similarly, if most of those who praise a man’s wit are in fact, inside that context, referring to his wit (d.s.), this is almost bound to become a new and distinguishable meaning of the word. The ambiguity of the Shakespearian passages is just what one might expect; the sort of thing that happens if we catch a new sense at the very moment when it is first branching off the parent stem.

Two less ambiguous passages illustrate a faint movement of the word away from its old sense in a direction which might finally lead to its meaning wit (d.s.). ‘Sharp and subtle discourses of wit’, says Hooker, ‘procure great applause, but being laid in the balance with that which the habit of sound experience plainly delivereth, they are over weighed’ (V, vii, 1). Burton defines wit as ‘acumen or subtilty, sharpness of invention’ (I, 1, 2, 10). Neither amounts to much. But the idea of levity (of the peu solide) which is there in Hooker, and that of sharpness in Burton, have perhaps some small significance. Wit is becoming something less staid and tranquil than intelligence.

It is in the second half of the seventeenth century that we find the most abundant and amusing evidences of the word’s drift towards its dangerous sense; amusing because they consist almost entirely of disclaimers. Everyone starts telling us what the word does not mean; a sure proof that it is beginning to mean just that.

1650: Davenant, describing something ‘which is not, yet is accompted, Wit’, includes in it ‘what are commonly 101 called Conceits, things that sound like the knacks or toyes of ordinary Epigrammatists’.[160]

1664: Flecknoe warns us that wit must not include ‘clenches (puns), quibbles, gingles, and such like trifles’.[161]

1667: Dryden tells us that wit does not consist of ‘the jerk or sting of an epigram nor the seeming contradiction of a poor antithesis . . . nor the jingle of a more poor paranomasia’.[162]

1668: Shadwell corrects those ignorant people who believed ‘that all the Wit in Playes consisted in bringing two persons upon the Stage to break Jests, and to bob one another, which they call Repartie’.[163]

1672: Dryden classifies ‘clenches’ as ‘The lowest and most grovelling kind of wit’.[164]

1700: Dryden says that ‘the vulgar judges . . . call conceits and jingles wit’.[165]

Clearly the thing which they deny to be wit, or admit only to be ‘the lowest and most grovelling’ species of it, is wit (d.s.). And this, as I have said, proves that wit (d.s.) was increasingly the current meaning of the word wit. To be sure, Dryden’s reference to ‘vulgar judges’, and perhaps the language of all these critics, might lead us to believe that a group of cultivated speakers were defending their own usage against a vulgarism perpetrated only by ‘lesser breeds without the law’. But it is no such thing. They themselves used wit in the sense they reprobate. 102 Watch Dryden off his guard when he is just using, not thinking about, the word.

‘As for comedy,’ he says, ‘repartee is one of its chief graces; the greatest pleasure of the audience is a chace of wit, kept up on both sides and swiftly managed.’[166] Or again, ‘They say the quickness of repartees in argumentative scenes receives an ornament from verse. Now what is more unreasonable than to imagine that a man should not only light upon the wit, but the rhyme too, upon the sudden.’[167] The ‘copiousness’ of Ovid’s ‘wit’ was such that he ‘often writ too pointedly for his subject’.[168] Only intolerable straining could give wit anything but its dangerous sense in such passages. What Dryden probably believed, and would certainly have wished others to believe, about his use of the word is not true. ‘Out of school’ he often talked like the ‘vulgar judges’.

Often, not always, wit-ingenium and wit (d.s.) were both equally parts of his vocabulary; and so, I suspect, was wit (old sense) too. The situation is common enough. You and I at nine o’clock any morning, poring over the pencilled washing bill presented by our bedmakers, complain ‘I can’t read the last figure’. At ten, during a supervision, we mention a figure (of rhetoric). At our elevenses we say to a friend that the young woman who has just left the tap-room has a fine figure. So then. Dryden, joined on his way to the coffee-house by an elderly friend, and asked whether it were not true that my Lord Clarendon was a man of great wit, would at once understand wit 103 (old sense). Seated an hour later among Templars and poets and discussing the nature of poetry he would use wit-ingenium. Yet, before the talk was out, if some bright youngster delighted them with brilliant repartee, he might praise that youngster’s wit (d.s.). He would slip in and out of the different meanings without noticing it. It is all ordinary and comfortable until one of the meanings happens to become strategically important in some controversy. A bad linguistic situation then results.

VI. THE AFFLICTIONS OF ‘WIT-INGENIUM’

The growing currency of wit (d.s.) would in any circumstances have endangered wit-ingenium. But the latter sense suffered from an internal weakness as well. It was a term of laudation; by attributing wit-ingenium to a man or calling him (in that sense) ‘a wit’, you praise him. This brings the distinction between word’s meaning and speaker’s meaning into play in a very acute form.

A Hottentot and a Dane might hammer out an agreed definition of beauty, and in that sense, lexically, ‘mean’ the same by it. Yet the one might continue, in a different sense, to ‘mean’ blubber lips, woolly hair, and a fat paunch while the other ‘meant’ a small mouth, silky hair, ‘white and red’, and a slender waist. And two men who agree about the (lexical) ‘meaning’ of comic would not necessarily find the same things funny.

This is even more obviously true of a word like genius. It may lexically ‘mean’ to all of us the mental quality, character, or state which produces, say, great literature. But we do not all think the same sorts of literature great. 104 We shall therefore attribute genius to quite different authors, and we shall include in our conception of genius different mental powers. Lexical agreement can co-exist with fierce disagreements about denotation.

In just this way there was, during the seventeenth and early eighteenth centuries, a wide agreement among critics—‘in school’, when they were on their guard—on the meaning of wit. They agreed that the ingenium sense was its true or proper meaning. Never, never (till, next moment, they forgot) would they consent to the meaning wit (d.s.). No; this noble word meant the essential faculty of the poet, the inner cause of excellence in writing. But while this lexical agreement still lasted taste began to change. Wit was the cause of excellence, but people began to think different things excellent. And no one was ready to give up the magic word wit. However little the new poetry resembled the old, those who claimed excellence for it claimed that it showed wit. As new shopkeepers who have ‘bought the goodwill’ of their predecessor’s business keep his name for a while over their door, so the literary innovators want to retain the prestige, almost the ‘selling-power’, of the consecrated word. It occurred to no one to say ‘The school of wit is over; we offer excellence of a different kind.’ They preferred to say ‘What we offer is “the real” or “true” wit’. Hence the constant, and linguistically barren, definings and re-definings of the word. They are merely tactical. The word has to be stretched and contracted so as to cover whatever you and your friends write or enjoy and to exclude what the enemy writes or enjoys.

105

Cowley ‘meant’ by wit the essential gift of the poet. But then, for him, the essential gift was the power to produce that concordia discors which has been called ‘Metaphysical Wit’ ever since Johnson’s day:

In a true piece of Wit all things must be,

Yet all things there agree,

As in the Ark, join’d without force or strife,

All Creatures dwelt; all creatures that had Life.[169]

Dryden also ‘meant’ by wit the essential gift of the poet. And in 1667 he defined this gift as ‘the faculty of imagination . . . which, like a nimble spaniel, beats over and ranges through the field of memory’.[170] His ideal is already a little different from Cowley’s; there is less emphasis on the discors, the heterogeneity of the things the poet unites. But ten years later he and Cowley are leagues apart, each ‘hull down’ to the other.[171] Wit is now ‘propriety of thoughts and words’. He produces this with some self-congratulation. He liked it so well that he repeated it in 1685.[172]

This definition, as Addison observes,[173] would commit us to the consequence, ‘Euclid was the greatest wit that ever set pen to paper’. It may also be asserted almost safely that no human being, when using the word wit to talk with and not talking about the word wit, has ever meant by it anything of the sort. Nor does Dryden himself anywhere make the slightest use of this definition; there is perhaps none to be made, since it leaves no room for any distinction in wit between the greatest literature 106 in the world and any competent piece of draughting. We might tax our brains for a long time to explain how a man of Dryden’s stature could have said anything so false to all actual usage, so useless, and so unsupported, if we did not realise its tactical function. He is thinking neither about what the word actually meant nor about what it could, in the interests of clarity and precision and general utility, be made to mean. It is a valuable vogue-word. Therefore a strong point in the critical battle. He wants to deny the enemy the use of it. What use, if any, his own side can make of it hereafter may be left for consideration. ‘Propriety’ is a garrison word; thrown in to exclude Ovid and Cowley and Cleveland from the highest poetical honours.

Pope also meant by wit the essential gift of the poet. But with him the wheel has come almost full circle. Wit, for Cowley, depends on the unexpected thought which yokes together ‘things by nature most unneighbourly’. For Pope it is the perfect expression of well-worn thoughts, the pellucidity and finality which rescue the obvious from neglect—

True Wit is Nature to advantage dress’d,

What oft was thought but ne’er so well express’d.[174]

But the tell-tale word is ‘true’. No one describes as ‘true happiness’ the life we all enjoy; it is just ‘happiness’. No one who is being agreeable calls himself our ‘true friend’; freedom and what Hegelians call ‘true freedom’ are almost mutually exclusive. If wit were the current name 107 for the thing Pope describes, then he would have called it simply wit, not true wit. The adjective shows that he is twisting the noun into a sense it never naturally bore.

In the story I have to tell Dryden and Pope cut a sufficiently poor figure; it is therefore only fair to add at once that this did not come about through any lack of intelligence. Both show elsewhere that they knew, and could have done, much better. ‘Ben Jonson . . . always writ properly and in the character required; and I will not contest further with my friends who call that wit; it being very certain that even folly itself, well represented is wit in a larger signification’.[175] Here we exchange dogmatism about what the word ought to mean for distinction between two of the things it actually meant. And Pope can write

Thus Wit, like faith, by each man is applied

To one small sect, and all are damn’d beside.[176]

In his own definition of ‘true wit’ he wrote from within one of the sects and on its behalf. Here he stands above the conflict; for a moment.

VII. HAPPY ENDING

These tactical definitions, having served their momentary purpose, were dropped by their inventors and rejected by other speakers. If they had any influence on the history of the language, they probably helped to hasten the death of the ingenium sense by diminishing its utility. But even this is very doubtful.

108

The ingenium sense had an external enemy in the increasing popularity of the dangerous sense. But it also had what we may call an internal enemy. Lexically, as I have said, wit-ingenium had long meant the essential gift of the poet. That was the word’s meaning. And the speaker’s meaning, of course, was the gift required for producing the sort of poetry the speaker approved. And ever since the last quarter of the sixteenth century most people had approved a pointed, figured, conceited sort of poetry. Gascoigne and the young Shakespeare and Du Bartas had not, any more than Cowley and Cleveland and Butler, been offering ‘what oft was thought’. Nor had Ovid, nor the young Dryden, nor always the young Milton. Modern critics rightly distinguish the Elizabethan from the ‘Metaphysical’ conceit; but all these poets, set against either medieval or eighteenth- and nineteenth-century poets, are a continuous dynasty. And by the time the mature Dryden and the young Pope are fighting for the recognition of a new kind of excellence, the long reign of that dynasty has associated wit-ingenium indissolubly with one kind of poetic ingenium. The speaker’s meaning has become the word’s meaning. The effort to appropriate the word wit to the new excellence is hopeless, just as now it would be hopeless to try to extend the word tragedy to cover plays (like the Helena, the Iphigenia in Tauris, or the Cid) that have a happy ending. It has been too long associated with deaths in Act V. So wit, as a term of praise for poetry, had been too long associated with a particular kind of poetry. And it was useful because it described the virtues of that kind, not of poetry 109 in general. In this sense the meaning that survived the critical controversies may be called wit-ingenium demoted, the thing described by Addison, when, correcting Locke, he says that wit is not merely ‘the assemblage of ideas . . . wherein can be found any resemblance or congruity’, because ‘every resemblance of ideas is not that which we call wit, unless it be such an one that gives delight and surprise’.[177] After that comes the perfection of Johnson, ‘a kind of discordia concors, a combination of dissimilar images, a discovery of occult resemblances in things apparently unlike’.[178] This belongs to a different world from the Popian and Drydenian definitions. Here is a man with no axe to grind, a man defining what he believes (no doubt rightly) to be the actual use of the word in one of its senses.

In one of its senses. For wit-ingenium even when thus demoted is still not quite synonymous with wit (d.s.). But they certainly have more in common with each other than either has with wit (old sense) or with any of the pseudo-senses the controversial critics gave the word. Both display the unexpected, the lively, the dexterous. Both, if disliked, are liable to be called ‘cleverness’, or ‘fireworks’. Thus, unforeseen, a very happy linguistic situation has come about. Outside literary circles wit means wit (d.s.). But those within the literary circles, while fully accepting wit (d.s.), have no difficulty in accepting the word wit (guarded with some such addition as metaphysical or baroque) as a name for the characteristic quality of Donne and Herbert. And most of us do not 110 feel that the one wit and the other are what Aristotle calls ‘things accidentally homonymous’. We have rather the conception of wit as something with a very wide range (from the Nocturnall upon S. Lucies Day to The Importance of Being Earnest) but also with a continuity throughout that range. Thus, after terrible danger, wit becomes once more a really useful word, as useful as it was in Anglo-Saxon. It enables us to distinguish; to point at this, and therefore not at that. In reaching this happy condition the word has, no doubt, had to abandon its large and lofty sense of ingenium. What has been (usefully) appropriated to one kind of literary excellence or even to one area of related excellences, cannot go on meaning literary excellence in general. As for its still more general meaning, its old sense, that survives in expressions like ‘God give you wit’. It is enabled to do so because it occurs in wholly un-literary contexts and therefore never clashes with wit as a critical term. Fallentis semita vitae; it lives by keeping out of its rival’s way.

111

5
FREE
[WITH ELEUTHERIOS, LIBERAL, FRANK ETC.]

The materials of this chapter will illustrate two principles mentioned in the Introduction. They are all moralised status-words. And they all show parallelism of semantic movement in different languages.

I. ‘ELEUTHEROS’

Eleutheros means ‘free’, not a slave. One can also be eleutheros apo, free from, pain, fear or the like. A community is eleutheros when it is autonomous; Xenophon can speak of two communities being eleutherous apo, free from, one another; mutually independent.[179] All this would be unimportant if the word had not taken on a secondary, a social-ethical, sense. To call a man eleutheros in the first sense merely identified his legal status; to call his behaviour eleutheros in the second was to say that it displayed the qualities which, on the Greek view, a freeman ought to have. There is also another adjective, eleutherios, which is used with this second meaning only. Eleutheros is used with both.

The character of the eleutheros (or eleutherios) is, of course, contrasted with that of the slave. It would be dangerous in modern English to say ‘with the servile 112 character’, for that would probably conjure up a false image. By a ‘servile’ man we mean, I take it, an abject, submissive man who cringes and flatters. That this was not the ancient idea of the typical slave is plain from the slaves in Greek and Roman comedy and also from the contrasts implied in the words we are now studying. It was a slave-girl who taunted Monica with her tippling, while quarrelling with her young mistress ut fit, ‘the way they do’.[180] The true servile character is cheeky, shrewd, cunning, up to every trick, always with an eye to the main chance, determined ‘to look after number one’. Figaro or Mrs Slipslop fill the requirements pretty well. Sam Weller has the right knowingness, the diamond-cut-diamond realism, but he is disinterested. Absence of disinterestedness, lack of generosity, is the hall-mark of the servile. The typical slave always has an axe to grind. Hence the miserably betrayed Philoctetes in Sophocles’ play (l. 1006) says to the cunning Odysseus ‘Oh you—you who never had a sound or eleutheron thought in your mind!’ Odysseus has done nothing without ‘an ulterior motive’.

It was of course recognised, as by Aristotle so by others, that servile status and servile character did not always coincide. Hence a fragment of Menander runs ‘Live in slavery with the spirit of a freeman (eleutherôs) and you will be no slave’.

Generosity being part of the freeman’s character, the abstract noun eleutheriotes can mean generosity about money, bountifulness, readiness to give; the word 113 generosity itself, as we noticed before, shows a very similar development. Aneleutheria, the opposite of eleutheriotes, of course means stinginess.[181]

II. ‘LIBER’

Latin liber and liberalis are related almost exactly as eleutheros and eleutherios. Liber is ‘free’, not a slave; or free, used of an inanimate object, in the sense of unconfined, unopposed. The sea, in Ovid, as opposed to the rivers, is the plain of freer (liberioris) water.[182] One’s mind or judgement can be liber when one is not ‘committed’ or bound by previous engagement or prejudice. Honest jurymen who come to the case with an ‘open’ mind are liberi solutique in Cicero’s Verrines, ‘free and without ties’. Conduct is liberalis when it is such as becomes a freeman. Justice, according to Cicero,[183] is the most magnificent virtue and most suitable-to-a-freeman (liberalis). This ethical sense is often specialised and narrowed to denote the quality which we still call liberality. ‘Liberales are the sort of people who ransom prisoners of war’.[184]

Since the word liberalis is metrically two trochees it can never occur in dactylic verse. In poetry, therefore, ingenuus (free-born) is used instead, with, I think, precisely the same range of meaning. That is, it may refer merely to status, but much more often has the ethical-social meaning; as when Juvenal says ‘a boy of ingenuus countenance, with an ingenuus modesty (pudor)’, in XI, 154. The passage is interesting in two ways: first, because this 114 boy was in fact a slave, and secondly because the pudor brings out by contrast the ancient idea of the typical slave. The slick waiters, alternately fawning and insolent, in the worst type of ‘posh’ hotel would have seemed to the ancients typically ‘servile’; the kind, unpretentious old servants whom men of my age can still remember (especially in the country) would not. The later history of the derivative ingenuous is also instructive; like a freeman, thence open, unsuspicious, ready to trust because trustworthy, thence (in the good sense) simple, thence too simple, credulous, finally fatuous, a dupe, a gull. Greek euethes, originally ‘good-natured’ but finally ‘silly’, shows the same development. So does silly itself, and innocent. These developments in fact embody the comment of the typical slave on the ingenuus, whose lack of suspicion he regards as folly. If Sam Weller had been a typical servus he would merely have despised (instead of both honouring and smiling at) the innocence of Mr Pickwick.

III. ‘FREE’

Like the Greek and Latin words this originally refers to legal status. The opposite is slave—theow in classical Anglo-Saxon, or, later, Old Norse thrael. All sons of free men, freora manna, are to be taught to read, says King Alfred in the preface to his version of the Cura Pastoralis. It also means ‘free’ in the physical sense, free to move. After her miraculous healing the blind woman in the old version of Bede, who had been led to the shrine by her maids, went home ‘freo on her own feet’ (IV, 10). These, the oldest senses of the word, are now, oddly enough, its 115 dangerous senses; for the others, those that correspond roughly to eleutherios and liberalis, are mainly obsolete.

I say ‘correspond roughly’ because there is a perceptible difference between the ancient and the English developments. Both may be described as ‘social-ethical’, but in the Greek and Roman words the ethical predominates and the social almost vanishes in the end. This is not so of English free. Its background is feudal, not republican; it belongs to a world in which manners were more elaborate than in antiquity and far more valued.

In Piers Plowman we read that Mede is married more for her money than for any virtue or beauty or any high kinde—any noble blood.[185] The B text at the corresponding point reads free kinde.[186] The adjectives are probably almost synonymous in this context. There need be no ethical implication in either; and the social pretension is higher than that of eleutheros or liberalis. Often the word refers neither to blood nor to morality but to manners, as when the thirteenth-century Floris and Blancheflor (l. 498) describes a burgher as ‘fre and curteys’, polite and courteous. Like the adjective kinde it tails off into the vaguest, most unspecified, laudation, so that Christ in the York Harrowing of Hell (l. 5) can say ‘mi Fader free’. It shows its fullest charge of meaning in Chaucer’s line ‘Trouthe and honour, fredom and courtesye’;[187] knightly behaviour, in which morality up to the highest self-sacrifice and manners down to the smallest gracefulness in etiquette were inextricably blended by the medieval ideal.

116

Inevitably, since ‘largesse’ is a most important aspect of fredom, this sense throws out the branch ‘munificent, open-handed’; ‘fre of hir goodes’, generous with their property,[188] or ‘to fre of dede’, over-liberal in its action.[189] This could also, however, be reached without going through the sense ‘noble, courteous’, simply from the sense ‘unrestrained’ (as in the translation of Bede); uninhibited, unchecked, in one’s dealings with one’s own property.

The larger sense is perhaps well brought out in Chaucer’s line ‘Free was daun John and namely of dispence’:[190] he had in general the manners of a gentleman, and especially in the way he spent his money. The Franklin’s Tale gives us a sort of competition in fredom (magnanimity, generosity) and hands over to the reader the problem ‘which was the moste free’.[191] Boccaccio in the corresponding passage asks who had shown the greatest liberalità.

From the sense ‘unrestrained’ another branch goes off. Behaviour which is informal, familiar, facile, the reverse of ‘stand-offish’, can be free. Thus Quarles says ‘The world’s a crafty strumpet . . . if thou be free she’s strange; if strange, she’s free’.[192] Hence a pejorative usage. One may be more familiar, less formal, than the social situation justifies, and may receive, as in Sheridan, the rebuff ‘Not so free, fellow’.[193] Finally free can almost mean ‘abusive’. ‘The mistress and the maid shall quarrel and give each 117 other very free language.’[194] ‘A freedom’ can likewise be an unwarranted breach of social restraint, a ‘liberty’ unduly ‘taken’, and even an indecency: ‘I do not know a more disagreeable character than a valetudinarian, who thinks he may do anything that is for his ease and indulges himself in the grossest freedoms’.[195]

It is probably by an influence from this sense that we should explain Shakespeare’s use of liberal to mean, in various senses, (too) ‘free-spoken’; as where the young wag in The Merchant is warned that his chatter among strangers may ‘show something too liberal’ (II, ii, 187).

Very distinct from all these, though doubtless springing from the idea of ‘unrestrained, not tied, not confined’, is free in the sense ‘costing nothing’ (Latin gratis and Greek dorean). Thus dorean is rendered as freely in the Authorised Version; ‘freely ye have received’, and, earlier, in the Wycliffite translation, freli.

IV. ‘FRANK’ AND ‘VILLAIN’

There is a sharp contrast between the histories of frank and free. The social-ethical meanings of free have vanished; but, for frank, only the ethical meaning, and that in a very narrowed sense, survives.

Originally frank is of course a national name—‘a Frank’. Its legal, social, and ethical meanings are ultimately derived from the state of affairs in Gaul after the Frankish conquest. Any man you met would probably be either a Frank, hence a conqueror, a warrior, and a landowner, or else a mere ‘native’, one of a subject race. 118 If the latter, he was (typically) a serf, an un-free peasant attached to an estate which had once been a Roman villa; he was in fact a villanus or vilains. Frank and villain (or frans and vilains) is the essential contrast.

English villain could still be used in its literal sense by Lancelot Andrewes: ‘they be men, and not beasts; freemen, and not villains’.[196] But long before his time it had dwindled into a term of abuse, and finally into a term of mere (i.e. unspecified) abuse: villain (d.s.), a synonym for ‘bad man’, useless except as a technical term in dramatic criticism (for ‘Shakespeare’s villains’ is a convenient enough expression). The process was of course gradual, and it is not easy to be sure what stage of it is represented by each occurrence of the word in the old texts.

At first its pejorative meaning was closely connected with its literal; the image of the actual vilains or peasant was still operative. Peasants, since we abolished them, have in this country been so idealised that we may go as far astray about the old overtones of ‘peasant’ as about the ancient idea of the servile character. We get an inkling of them when Love, in the Romance of the Rose, says ‘no villain or butcher’ has ever been allowed to kiss his lips (l. 1938). He goes on to say that the villain is brutal (fel), pitiless, disobliging, and unfriendly (ll. 2086-7). If you would avoid vilanie, the peasant character, you must imitate courteous Gawain, not surly Kay (ll. 2093 f.). Danger is later described as a vilains; he leaps suddenly from his hiding place, huge, dark, bristly, with blazing eyes, loud and violent (ll. 2920 f.). But notice that while 119 vilains is still thus closely connected with the image of the actual peasant, it quite clearly refers to a psychological type, not to an actual rank. Love takes care to tell us that ‘vilanie makes the vilains’ (l. 2083). Theoretically, one who was a vilains by status might not have the vice of vilanie; certainly many a man who is not a vilains by status will be guilty of it. Churl, itself originally a status word, would be the nearest English equivalent to Old French vilains in this sense, if it had not come to lay more emphasis on niggardliness in particular than on the generally sullen and uncooperative character of the peasant.[197] Boor is perhaps now our best translation.

The noun vilein is of doubtful occurrence in Chaucer, but vileinye is common. The central area of its meaning is rudeness, bad manners. The Knight never ‘said vileinye’, spoke rudely, to anyone (A. 70). Chaucer hopes that his setting down the bawdy tales will not be counted against him as vileinye (l. 726). The young roisterers in the Pardoner’s Tale are reproved for speaking vileinye to an old man (C. 740). By an easy transition, to dispraise or vilify anything is to speak vileinye of it; the Wife of Bath asks why one should speak vileinye ‘of bigamye or of octogamye’ (D. 34) or of Lameth (D. 53). Hence a shame or indignity done to anything, like Creon’s refusal to permit the burial of the enemy dead (A. 941), can be a vileinye.

We get nearer to a purely ethical sense when the Wife of Bath argues that if nobility were really transmissible by heredity, then those of a good stock would never cease to practise gentillesse nor begin practising ‘villeinye or vyce’ 120 (D. 1133-8). But the context still attaches the word very closely not to moral defects in general but to those moral defects which were felt to be especially inappropriate in the highest ranks—the opposites of gentillesse. Twice we find rape described as villeinye. The wife of Hasdrubal committed suicide to make sure that no Roman ‘dide hir vileinye’ (F. 1404), and Tarquin is asked in an apostrophe how he could have done Lucretia ‘this vilanye’.[198] But note the preceding lines. He ought to have acted as a lord and a ‘verray knight’, instead of which he has ‘doon dispyt to chivalrye’. Rape will naturally be the first of all moral offences to be called vileinye because, besides being a sin against the Christian law, it is the direct antithesis of gentillesse, of courtesy and of deference to ladies. Tarquin’s sin is a vilein’s act because it is, as our fathers, if not we, would say, ‘the act of a cad’. Indeed the word cad, with its contemporary semantic wobble between social and moral condemnation, is a good enough parallel to vileinye in this sense. And once vileinye means something like ‘caddishness’ it is already on the downward path which will finally lead it to become a word of mere, unspecified opprobrium. Once or twice in Chaucer it has almost reached this stage. When the act of those enemies who had beaten the wife of Melibeus and mortally wounded his daughter is described as a vileinye (B. 2547), or John warns Aleyn that the miller is a dangerous man who might do them a vileinye (A. 4191), the content of the word is perhaps hardly more precise than ‘a rotten trick’ or ‘a bad turn’. In the Second Nun’s Tale, when we 121 hear that no one can see the rose and lily garlands brought by the angel unless he ‘be chaast and hate vileinye’ (G. 231), perhaps we have reached a purely ethical meaning.

In the Elizabethan drama villain, and the associated words, are, so to speak, treacherous. At first the modern reader in most contexts will give them the dangerous sense without hesitation. Because they are opprobrious, that sense will always seem to fit the context; that is why it is so dangerous. ‘Remorseless, treacherous, lecherous, kindless villain!’;[199] ‘I never loved my brother in my life’—‘More villain thou’;[200] ‘Some villain hath done me wrong’[201]—what should all these be but villain (d.s.)? Perhaps they all are. But it is not absolutely certain.

Antipholus of Syracuse describes his man Dromio as ‘a trusty villain’ whose ‘merry jests’ often cheer him up.[202] We have here of course the affectionate use of an opprobrious term in reverse—like ‘a trusty rogue’. But it is hard to believe that the opprobrium stored in the term before it is reversed can be as strong as that of villain (d.s.). Something more like ‘rogue’ or (in older usage) ‘wretch’, or ‘rascal’. And ‘rascal’—certainly not villain (d.s.)—is surely the sense required when Petruchio repeatedly calls his man Grunio a villain, and once a knave.[203] Again, in Measure for Measure (V, i, 264) the luckless Lucio says that Friar Lodowick ‘spoke most villanous speeches of the Duke’. The point of the joke is that it was Lucio himself who had spoken those speeches, as no one knows better than the Duke. And they were not those of a villain (d.s.). 122 He was not plotting the Duke’s murder or deposition, only telling ‘pretty tales’, talking bawdy about his betters. His speeches were, in fact, vileinye in Chaucer’s rather than in the modern sense; rude, scandalous.

Since words mean many things in the same period, these usages do not of course disprove the interpretation villain (d.s.) in the previous passages from Hamlet, As You Like It and Lear. But they provide the background against which its probability can be judged. I am inclined, myself, to think that villain (d.s.) need not be fully present in any of them. It may be present in all as the speaker’s meaning. The speaker certainly regards the other party as what we would call a villain; but I am not certain that he selects this particular term of abuse because it already (lexically) has the meaning ‘very wicked man’. The purpose of all opprobrious language is, not to describe, but to hurt—even when, like Hamlet, we make only the shadow-passes of a soliloquised combat. We call the enemy not what we think he is but what we think he would least like to be called. Hence extreme hatred may select the word villain precisely because it is not yet merely moral but still carries some implication of ignoble birth, coarse manners, and ignorance. For all except the best men would rather be called wicked than vulgar. Compare the scene where Somerset calls Suffolk away from the de jure Duke of York with the words ‘Away! . . . We grace the yeoman by conversing with him’.[204]

All this I admit to be uncertain. But there is one place where I very greatly hope that villain has hardly any of 123 the dangerous sense in it. The opening soliloquy of Richard III does not, on any view, show Shakespeare at his subtlest. But the crudity of ‘I am determined to prove a villain’ (I, i, 30) is, even on that level, almost comic if Richard means villain (d.s.). But if we dare suppose that the word has predominantly—or, better still, exclusively—its older sense, the line is immeasurably improved. For then, Richard, having produced as good, and contemptuous, a parody as his distorted body can of those who ‘court an amorous looking glass’, suddenly relapses into himself, looks as clumsy, as coarse, as uncouth as he knows how—becomes the very image of the vilains, fixes the audience with a glance of ogre-ish glee, and says in effect ‘Well; since I can’t be a lounge-lizard, I’ll be—gad, I’ll be—a Tough’.

Some other usages, which obviously come by hyperbole, are consistent with almost any meaning of the word. Such are ‘a villainous house for fleas’, ‘villainous smell’, ‘villainous melancholy’, or ‘villainously cross-gartered’. These will surprise no one who remembers how, at various periods, every inconvenience or discomfort, has been called scurvy, abominable, shocking, incredible or shattering.

In Old French, frans, the form which, frank assumed, can mean free, unencumbered. There is a line quoted by Chalcidius ‘When you have laid aside your body and soar free (liber) to the sky’;[205] the Romance of the Rose (l. 5030) translates ‘You will go frans into the holy air’. This usage is found also in English; Lord Berners in his 124 version of Huon writes ‘he and all his companye shal depart frank and free at their pleasure’ (XLIII).

Its social-ethical sense once had pretty much the same range as that of free. The god of love, in the Romance of the Rose, says that the servant when he accepts must be courteous and frans (l. 1939). The quality which the frans has is of course franchise (courtesy, gentle manners, the gentle heart) both in French and English; among Gawain’s virtues are ‘franchise and fellowshipe’.[206] But later usage restricted the word to a sense which may owe something both to the idea of ‘unrestrained’ and to that of the noble or chivalrous. This double implication, or double semantic root, may have helped the sense in question to triumph. The frank person is unencumbered by fears, calculations, and an eye to the main chance; he also shows the straightforwardness and boldness of a noble nature. Hence ‘with frank and with uncurbed plainness’[207] or ‘bearing with frank appearance their purposes towards Cyprus’.[208]

Like free, it too can mean gratis, not to be paid for; in Mother Hubbards Tale, we find ‘Thou hast it wonne for it is of frank gift’ (l. 531). This sense long survived in ‘the frank’ which members of Parliament were once entitled to put on their letters.

V. AN OBSOLETE BRANCH-LINE

Like eleutheria and libertas, freedom and franchise can of course mean the legal freedom of a community. But the ancient words are used chiefly, if not entirely, in reference 125 to the freedom of a state. The contrast implied is sometimes between autonomy and subjection to a foreign power; sometimes between the freedom of a republic and the rule of a despot. The medieval words nearly always refer to something different; to the guaranteed freedoms or immunities (from royal or baronial interference) of a corporate entity which cuts across states, like the Church, or which exists within the state, like a city or guild. Thus Gower says a knight should defend ‘The common right and the franchise of Holy Churche’;[209] or Shakespeare, ‘If you deny it let the danger light upon your city’s freedom’.[210]

This led to a development unparalleled, I believe, in the ancient languages. By becoming a member of any corporation which enjoys such freedom or franchise you of course come to share that freedom or franchise. You become a freeman of, or receive the freedom of, that city; or you become ‘free of the Grocers’.[211] These are familiar. But a further development along this line is more startling. Freedom can mean simply ‘citizenship’, and when the centurion tells Saint Paul that he had paid a lot of money to acquire Roman citizenship (politeia), the Authorised Version says ‘At a great price obtained I this freedom’.[212] Philemon Holland translating Suetonius writes ‘Unlesse they might be donati civitate . . . enioye the fraunchises and freedom of Rome’. This meaning is fossilised in the surviving English use of franchise to mean the power of voting, conceived as the essential mark of full citizenship.

126

VI. ‘LIBERAL’ AS A CULTURAL TERM

We had brought the ancient words to a social and ethical sense; it remains to consider the all-important cultural meaning which grew from it.

The freeman, and still more the eleutherios or liberalis who not only is but ought to be a freeman, has not only his characteristic virtues but his characteristic occupations. Some of these are necessary; statesmanship, says Pseudo-Plato, is the most liberal (eleutheriotaten) of studies.[213] But the idea that leisure occupations, things done for their own sake and not for utility, are especially eleuthera, soon comes into play. It is perhaps present when Xenophon says ‘They have a square (agora) called the Free (eleuthera) Square from which tradespeople and their noises and vulgarities (apeirokaliai) are excluded’.[214] The tradespeople need not be, and probably are not, slaves. But they are engaged in activities which have no value except in so far as they contribute to some end outside themselves. The contrast becomes explicit when Aristotle says in the Rhetoric ‘of one’s possessions those which yield some profit are the most useful, but those which exist only to be enjoyed are eleutheria’. This is the first step. Only he who is neither legally enslaved to a master nor economically enslaved by the struggle for subsistence, is likely to have, or to have the leisure for using, a piano or a library. That is how one’s piano or library is more liberal, more characteristic of one’s position as a freeman, than one’s coal-shovel or one’s tools.

127

But there is a further development, which we owe (I believe) entirely to Aristotle; a brilliant conceit. (There is no reason why we should not attribute a conceit to him; he was a wit, and a dressy man, as well as a philosopher.) It comes in the Metaphysics.[215] ‘We call a man free whose life is lived for his own sake not for that of others. In the same way philosophy is of all studies the only free one; for it alone exists for its own sake.’

Here is an astonishing change. Up till now a study could be free because it was the characteristic occupation of a freeman. Aristotle now makes it ‘free’ in a quite new sense; namely, by analogy. It is a free study because it holds among other studies the same privileged position which the freeman holds among other men. The conceit is all the better for taking up into itself the much simpler idea that disinterestedness is an essential part of the ‘free’ character. The free study seeks nothing beyond itself and desires the activity of knowing for that activity’s own sake. That is what the man of radically servile character—give him what leisure and what fortune you please—will never understand. He will ask, ‘But what use is it?’ And finding that it cannot be eaten or drunk, nor used as an aphrodisiac, nor made an instrument for increasing his income or his power, he will pronounce it—he has pronounced it—to be ‘bunk’.

How far Aristotle’s ideal is from a mere dilettantism can best be seen by giving it the background which two other passages supply. In Metaphysics we learn that the organisation of the universe resembles that of a household, 128 in which ‘no one has so little chance to act at random as the free members. For them everything or almost everything proceeds according to a fixed plan (tetaktai), whereas the slaves and domestic animals contribute little to the common end and act mostly at random.’[216] The attitude of any slave-owning society is and ought to be repellent to us, but it is worth while suppressing that repulsion in order to get the picture as Aristotle saw it. Looking from his study window he sees the hens scratching in the dust, the pigs asleep, the dogs hunting for fleas; the slaves, any of them who are not at that very moment on some appointed task, flirting, quarrelling, cracking nuts, playing dice, or dozing. He, the master, may use them all for the common end, the well-being of the family. They themselves have no such end, nor any consistent end, in mind. Whatever in their lives is not compelled from above is random—dependent on the mood of the moment. His own life is quite different; a systematised round of religious, political, scientific, literary and social activities; its very hours of recreation (there’s an anecdote about them) deliberate, approved and allowed for; consistent with itself. But what is it in the structure of the universe that corresponds to this distinction between Aristotle, self-bound with the discipline of a freeman, and Aristotle’s slaves, negatively free with a servile freedom between each job and the next? I think there is no doubt of the answer. It is the things in the higher world of aether which are regular, immutable, consistent; those down here in the air that are subject to change, and chance and 129 contingence.[217] In the world, as in the household, the higher acts to a fixed plan; the lower admits the ‘random’ element. The free life is to the servile as the life of the gods (the living stars) is to that of terrestrial creatures. This is so not because the truly free man ‘does what he likes’, but because he imitates, so far as a mortal can, the flawless and patterned regularity of the heavenly beings, like them not doing what he likes but being what he is, being fully human as they are divine, and fully human by his likeness to them. For the crown of life—here we break right out of the cautious modesty of most Greek sentiment—is not ‘being mortal, to think mortal thoughts’ but rather ‘to immortalise as much as possible’ and by all means to live according to the highest element in oneself.[218]

Of course humanity is not often on the Aristotelian height. The eleutheria mathemata of the Greeks, the liberalia studia or liberales artes of the Latins are soon taken over by the curricula and every teacher or student knows which they are; one no longer needs to think why they are called liberal. You need merely enumerate: ‘Arts’, says Cicero, ‘which include liberales et ingenuae knowledges, such as Geometry, Music, the knowledge of letters and poets and whatever is said about natural objects, human manners and politics’.[219] One even meets the idea (strange to those who have studied the lives of the Humanists) that the pursuit of such studies tends to improve one’s behaviour: ‘to have learned well the 130 liberal arts’ (ingenuas, because it comes in a hexameter) ‘softens the manners and banishes ferocity’.[220] Finally, in the Middle Ages, the Liberal Arts settle down into the well known list of seven—grammar, dialectic, rhetoric, music, arithmetic, geometry, and astronomy. Arithmetic might hardly have won its place if Aristotle’s idea of the liberal had been kept steadily in view.

That idea is, however, still operative in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries in the conception of an inquisitiveness which is ‘generous’ or ‘noble’ or ‘liberal’ because it seeks knowledge for its own sake. Johnson speaks of ‘such knowledge as may justly be admired in those who have no motive to study but generous curiosity’,[221] and praises Boswell, back from Corsica, as one ‘whom a wise and noble curiosity has led where perhaps no native of his country ever was before’.[222] Macaulay says that the Jesuits, as missionaries, ‘wandered to countries which neither mercantile avidity nor liberal curiosity had impelled any stranger to explore’.[223]

The liberal motive is here contrasted equally with the religious and the mercantile. This suggests a problem for those who wish to embrace both the Christian and the Aristotelian scheme. What excellence can either ideal concede to the other? The only nineteenth-century author, so far as I know, who fully faced the question was Newman, in a very firm piece of thinking which makes clear how, in his view, that which is necessarily subordinate 131 has nevertheless its own relative autonomy and its own proper excellence—

That alone is liberal knowledge which stands on its own pretensions, which is independent of sequel . . . refuses to be informed (as it is called) by any end. The most ordinary pursuits have this specific character if they are self-sufficient and complete; the highest lose it when they minister to something beyond them. . . . If, for instance, Theology, instead of being cultivated as a contemplation, be limited to the purposes of the pulpit or be represented by the catechism, it loses—not its usefulness, not its divine character, not its meritoriousness (rather it increases those qualities by such charitable condescension) but it does lose the particular attribute which I am illustrating; just as a face worn by tears and fasting loses its beauty. . . . And thus it appears that even what is supernatural need not be liberal, nor need a hero be a gentleman, for the plain reason that one idea is not another idea.[224]

Unless followed by the word ‘education’, liberal has now lost this meaning. For that loss, so damaging to the whole of our cultural outlook, we must thank those who made it the name, first of a political, and then of a theological, party. The same irresponsible rapacity, the desire to appropriate a word for its ‘selling-power’, has often done linguistic mischief. It is not easy now to say at all in English what the word conservative would have said if it had not been ‘cornered’ by politicians. Evangelical, intellectual, rationalist, and temperance have been destroyed in the same way. Sometimes the arrogation is so outrageous that it fails; the Quakers have not killed the word friends. And sometimes so many different people 132 grab at the coveted word for so many different groups or factions that, while it is spoiled for its original purpose, none of the grabbers achieve secure possession. Humanist is an example; it will probably end by being a term of eulogy as vague as gentleman.

We cannot stop the verbicides. The most we can do is not to imitate them.

133

6
SENSE
[WITH SENTENCE, SENSIBILITY, AND SENSIBLE]

I. INTRODUCTORY

Everyone who speaks English is familiar with two meanings for the word sense: (a) ordinary intelligence or ‘gumption’, and (b) perception by sight, hearing, taste, smell or touch, which I shall call aesthesis. In our individual linguistic histories gumption is undoubtedly the earlier meaning. We had all been told to ‘have sense’, or asked why we ‘had not more sense’, years before we ever heard sense used to mean aesthesis. The aesthesis meaning belongs to a comparatively late, bookish, and abstract stratum of our vocabulary.

On the other hand there is no evidence that we reach the meaning aesthesis by a metonymy or any other kind of extension from the meaning gumption. In modern English the two meanings are not at all related as parent and child. They can be explained only by the pre-English history of the word; not of course that most English speakers have known or cared anything about that history, but that in their daily usages they have unconsciously availed themselves of the situation it had created.

Of the thousands who use the word sense, sometimes to mean gumption, and sometimes to mean aesthesis, only 134 the tiny minority who are interested in language ever notice that they are doing so. A sudden transition from the one meaning to the other would affect most speakers like a pun.

II. ‘SENTIRE’

Sense is from sensus, the noun that goes with the verb sentire, and at the verb our story must begin. Its central area of meaning seems to me to have been something like ‘to experience, learn by experience, undergo, know at first hand’. ‘Catiline’, says Cicero, ‘is going to learn, going to find out (sentiet), that the consuls in this town are wide awake.’[225] That is, he is going to learn by (bitter) experience. The braggart in Phaedrus (V, ii) assures his fellow traveller that he will pursue the man who has robbed them both and ‘see that he learns’ (curabo sentiat) what sort of people he has meddled with. The English would be ‘I’ll show him’. As prices went up, says Tacitus, the mass of the people gradually came to know (sentire) the ills of war;[226] as we might say ‘began to find out what war really means’. It can also be used of another sort of first-hand experience; that is, like know in the Authorised Version, it can mean ‘to have carnal knowledge of, sexual intercourse with’. Thus Ovid, addressing Neptune, can say ‘Ceres knew (sensit) you in the form of a horse, Medusa knew (sensit) you as a bird, Melantho knew (sensit) you as a dolphin’.[227] In some contexts English see would be a good translation, but with no precise restriction to visual experience (cf. ‘He has seen 135 active service’), so that we could render Horace’s lines ‘With you I saw (sensi) the fight at Philippi and the sauve-qui-peut rout’.[228] The same author can use sentire—perhaps with less of conscious personification than we suppose—of a vine which ‘will not feel (sentiet) the withering south-wind’.[229] For feel we could equally well put get, catch, suffer, or perhaps, in older English, taste. But we should have to use see again for the line where Virgil’s Venus saw (sensit) that Juno had been talking disingenuously.[230] Strictly speaking, no doubt, such a ‘seeing’ would involve rapid half-unconscious inferences, but it would be felt as immediate; and certainly as first-hand compared with any knowledge of your opponent’s motives which you could get from a report by a third party.

Now the two most obvious instances of knowledge at first hand or by experience are (a) that of our own conscious psychological state at the moment, and (b) that which we receive by sight, hearing, touch, smell and taste. We shall not therefore be surprised if sentire is used of both. I know or perceive or (as the French would say) experiment, my present thought and emotions; sentio will do for that. I also know or perceive or experiment the hardness of this pen, the white of this paper, and the temperature of the room; sentio will do for that too. Thus from the beginning the verb has a tendency to bifurcation of meaning. How soon, or whether at any time, the Romans felt it to have what we should call ‘two meanings’ 136 is a question for classical scholars. We, who are concerned with the later developments, may certainly (in view of those later developments) say that the word is already bifurcated in classical Latin. We shall therefore distinguish sentire (A) from sentire (B). Sentire (A) has what may loosely (with no pretence at philosophy) be called the introspective meaning; Sentire (B), the aesthesis meaning.

III. ‘SENTIRE (A)’

Although sentire (A) is itself a product of bifurcation, within it another bifurcation immediately threatens us. Of this subordinate bifurcation I do not think the Romans were aware. Our more analytic minds impose it. As translators we have to decide in each case whether we are going to render sentio (A) by ‘I feel’ or ‘I think’. Very often we cannot decide, and possibly a Roman would not have understood what we are asking. At the end of the first chapter of his Histories (Book I) Tacitus congratulates himself on the felicity of a period in which you can sentire (feel? or think?) what you please and say quid sentias (what you think? or feel?). Seneca says to Lucilius, ‘I want my letters to run just as my talk would run if we were sitting or walking together . . . if possible I would rather show than say quid sentiam (what I feel? or think?) . . . This at least I’d like to assure you of: my sentire (my really thinking? my feeling? my really meaning?) all I said’.[231] Cicero says of some philosopher ‘If he sensit as he speaks, he is depraved’.[232] If he meant what he says? If he felt as he talks? If he thought as he talks?

137

There is an apparent (but, I think, only apparent) parallel to this in modern colloquial English, ‘I feel that last step in your argument is a bit doubtful’. But feel here is almost certainly used as a polite litotes, a deliberate understatement. To avoid the rudeness of saying ‘I have detected a non sequitur which I will now demonstrate’, we feign that what is really, or what we take to be, a rational perception, is merely a fugitive emotion. The mixture of think and feel in sentire has almost certainly nothing to do with understatement.

There is, then, a central semantic area of sentire (A) which resists our efforts to dichotomise. But there are also usages which fall neatly on one side or other of the line we want to draw, giving us sentire (A1) (to feel) and sentire (A2) (to think).

Sentire (A1) can be illustrated from the famous couplet in Catullus: ‘I love and hate. You ask me how? I don’t know; but I feel it (sentio) happening and it is torture’ (LXXXV). So also in Seneca, ‘to feel (sentire) grief at the loss of a friend’.[233] The usage is not, however, very common.

Sentire (A2), on the other hand, is common and unambiguous. The verb here means not only to think or opine, but to ‘take a view’, to arrive at an opinion and give formal expression to it. Thus in Cicero, ‘I joined in opinion (assensi) with those who seemed to take the mildest opinion’ (lenissime sentire);[234] or in Aulus Gellius, ‘if the judges take a view, come to a decision (senserint), in my favour’. This meaning was of great importance for later linguistic history.

138

IV. ‘SENTIRE (B)’

This is the aesthesis meaning: to perceive by one of the ‘senses’. It is quite simple and need not detain us. ‘We perceive (sentimus) the various smells of things’, says Lucretius (I, 298), or ‘You can perceive (sentire) the sound’ (IV, 560). It is often assumed, I fancy, that this is the oldest meaning of sentire, but that assumption would not make the general history of the word easier to understand.

V. THE NOUNS

The verb sentire is privileged to have two nouns. One is sentientia (like conscientia with conscire) which in classical Latin has become sententia. The other is sensus. There is a difference between them. Sententia is the noun of sentire only in its A-meaning; but sensus is the noun of sentire in all its meanings.

VI. ‘SENTENTIA’ AND ‘SENTENCE’

1. Since sentire (A2) means to think or opine, a man’s opinion, what he thinks, is his sententia. This usage is familiar to everyone from the often-quoted Terentian quot homines, tot sententiae, ‘There are as many opinions as there are men’. Middle English sentence retains this meaning; ‘the commune sentence of the peple false is’.[235] By an important specialisation, sententia can mean the considered, final opinion of a judge: ‘Cato as judge gave his sententia,’ says Cicero.[236] Hence English sentence comes to mean the judge’s decision about the punishment and 139 finally the punishment itself—‘the sentence was death’. This is an excellent example of the merely homophonic status to which the different uses of a word are finally reduced. If you said ‘Jeremy Taylor can boast the longest sentence of any English writer’ and someone replied ‘Poor Wilde had a longer one’, this would be a pure pun.

2. A man’s opinion or sententia, what he thinks, can of course be distinguished from the words in which he expresses it. From this point of view sententia comes to signify meaning as opposed to words, content as opposed to form. ‘The Stoic doctrine about living according to Nature has, I believe, the following meaning (sententia)’, says Cicero.[237] Old French and Middle English sentence can both be used in the same way. ‘This is the meaning (sentence) of Plato’s words in French’, says Jean de Meung.[238] Chaucer boasts of giving us ‘playnly every word’ of Troilus’ song and not merely the sentence, the drift or meaning.[239]

3. If a man’s meaning can be contrasted with his words, so the meaning of words can of course be contrasted with their sound. Thus we find Lucretius saying that you may be able to hear the sound of someone talking in the next room when you cannot make out the sententia or meaning (IV, 561).

4. Because sententia is ‘meaning’, the minimum unit of speech or writing which has a complete meaning can be a sententia. Thus Quintilian says the whole point of 140 Lysias’ style would have been lost if he had had a system (ratio) for ‘beginning and ending sententias, his sentences’ (IX, iv).

5. When we say that an utterance is ‘full of meaning’ we do not merely claim that none of it is meaningless; we claim that it is profound, worth chewing on, ‘significant’. Just in the same way sententia can signify not bare ‘meaning’ but ‘depth of meaning’, meaningfulness, pith, profundity. Speaking of the old maxim ‘know thyself’, Cicero says it was attributed to a god because it has so much sententia—goes so deep, has ‘so much in it’.[240] This is an important usage of Middle English sentence. The speech of Chaucer’s clerk was ‘short and quik and full of heigh sentence’;[241] economical, full of life, and pregnant. There was no dead wood.

6. Both the preceding usages may have helped sententia to the meaning ‘maxim, saw, apophthegm, aphorism’. Quintilian rightly regards sententia, in this usage, as the equivalent of Greek gnome (VIII, v). A style full of sententiae is a gnomic style. English sentence long retained this as one of its commonest meanings: ‘a sentence or an old man’s saw’, we read in The Rape of Lucrece (l. 244). Overbury’s ‘Meere Scholer’ is one who ‘speaks sentences’. As late as Johnson’s time we find ‘A Greek writer of sentences’, an aphorist.[242]

From sententia meaning a maxim, through sententiosus, we get our adjective sententious. Originally it had no derogatory implication. In his Second Sermon on the Lord’s 141 Prayer Latimer observes ‘it is better to say it sententiously one time than to run over it an hundred times with humbling and mumbling’. To say it sententiously is to say it meaningfully, thinking of what you say. When Milton describes the Greek tragedians as teaching by ‘brief sententious precepts’ he is referring simply to their gnomic manner.[243] By Fanny Burney’s time the word is beginning to have its modern force; in Caecilia (IV, 1) the truth of a remark can ‘palliate’ its ‘sententious absurdity’. The development had long been prepared, for ever since the sixteenth century the conversation of those who dealt much in saws and adages had been despised. Overbury’s ‘mere scholar’ we had a moment ago; you may add Donne’s clownish mistress, ‘natures lay Ideot’, whose talk, till he taught her better, had consisted of ‘broken proverbs and torne sentences’.[244] The word has also, I suspect, been infected by the phonetic proximity of pretentious. A word needs to be very careful about the phonetic company it keeps. The old meaning of obnoxious has been almost destroyed by the combined influence of objectionable and noxious, and that of deprecate by depreciate, and that of turgid by turbid.

VII. ‘SENSUS’ AND ‘SENSE’

The least specialised meaning of this noun seems to me to correspond exactly to that given for the verb in paragraph II. Sensus is first-hand experience, immediate awareness of one’s own mental and emotional content. We have sensus of that which is erlebt. Ovid in 142 exile envies Niobe for being turned into stone because she thus lost the sensus of her sorrows.[245] Cicero’s own sensus tells him how strong love between brothers can be.[246] In English he might have said ‘I know from what I feel myself or ‘My own heart tells me’. But it would be better to render it ‘I know because I’ve tried’ (or ‘because I’ve been through it’), for we must not fix a too narrowly emotional meaning on sensus. We want a meaning which will cover another Ciceronian passage. In the Republic (I, xxxviii) one disputant says to another ‘Use the evidence of your own sensus’. ‘My sensus of what?’ comes the reply. The required sensus turns out to be that of controlling anger by reason. In this context it is hardly possible to translate sensus by any word but ‘experience’; in others ‘awareness’ or (sometimes) ‘consciousness’ will do.

Such unspecified awareness is of course a common meaning of sense. ‘Of the highest vertue’, says Bacon, the common people ‘have no sense or perceiving at all’;[247] compare Wordsworth’s ‘sense sublime Of something far more deeply interfused’. In much the same way we are said to have or lack a sense of honour, decency, danger, inferiority, or almost what you will. This meaning now exists, in an almost fossilised condition, in ‘sense of humour’. We hardly remember that this was originally an awareness of humours (idiosyncrasies) in our neighbours.

So much for the central, hardly differentiated, meaning of the word. We have now to follow its A- and B-bifurcations—its intellectual and sensory meanings.

143

VIII. ‘SENSUS’ AND ‘SENSE (A)’

1. Like sententia, it can mean opinion. ‘His sensus about politics pleases me greatly’, says Cicero—I like his political views.[248] This may be the meaning of sense when Shakespeare says, ‘For in my sense ’tis happiness to die’.[249] It is certainly so when Macaulay speaks about ‘the unanimous sense of the meeting’ or ‘the sense of the best jurists’.[250]

2. Sensus is also used in the Vulgate to render Greek nous. Nous is a hard word. When St Paul says ‘Every one must be fully confident in his own nous[251] and the Vulgate translates ‘Every one must be full to overflowing (abundet) in his own sensus’, one is tempted to equate nous with opinion—in which cases sensus would have exactly the same force as in the preceding examples. But I think nous comes to mean something like opinion only because it means mind (as we also, till lately, could have said ‘I told him my mind on the question’) and our next example confirms this. St Paul speaks of the nous which God cannot accept;[252] Vulgate translates this as reprobum sensum. Nous and sensus here mean something like ‘frame’ or ‘state’ of mind. Both passages are important for their effect on the vernaculars. Thanks to the first, it was good French centuries later for Descartes to say chacun abonde si fort en son sens;[253] thanks to the second, Burton can say ‘They are in a reprobate sense, they cannot 144 think a good thought’,[254] and Milton, ‘Insensate left or to sense reprobate’.[255] In all three passages this meaning is derived, ultimately from the Vulgate. It entered English through the Rheims version of 1582, which reads at xiv. 5 ‘let every man abound in his own sense’, and at i. 28 ‘a reprobate sense’. That English and Protestant authors, one of them a good Greek scholar, should depend for a scriptural phrase either on Vulgate or Rheims will seem strange to many. Very ill-grounded ideas about the exclusive importance of the Authorised Version in the English biblical tradition are still widely held.

3. Like sententia, sensus, and of course sense, signify the meaning of a word. ‘This was the sensus of the word’, says Ovid.[256] The whole of this book is about the senses of words. Here we have a usage from which, even without the help of developments still to be noticed, the meaning ‘gumption’ might have been developed. ‘Talk sense’ and ‘Have sense’ are very similar rebukes. But the first follows easily from sense signifying meaning: ‘Say things that have some meaning, stop uttering the non-significant.’ ‘He has no sense’ could have arisen (though the actual history is more complicated) as an ellipsis of ‘His conversation has no sense’.

4. By exaggeration sense (meaning) is often used loosely for important or pertinent meaning, so that, like sententia, it is equivalent to ‘depth of meaning’. The passage from Overbury, which I gave in a truncated form above, runs in full, ‘A meere scholar speaks sentences more familiarly 145 than sense’. I do not think this means that his discourse was often meaningless, in the strict use of the word—only that it was, as we say, ‘gas’, there was ‘nothing in it’. Similarly when Herbert says of the sermon

if all want sense,

God takes a text, and preacheth patience,[257]

he hardly envisaged a preacher who talked actual gibberish; the ‘want of sense’ would be vapidity, emptiness, ignorance or the like. This usage also can clearly help us towards the meaning ‘gumption’.

5. Like sententia, sensus can also mean a grammatical sentence. ‘It is best by far’, says Quintilian, ‘to end the sensus with a verb’ (IX, iv). So in Dryden, ‘Mr Waller first showed us to conclude the sense most commonly in distichs’.[258]

6. To lack awareness (sensus), to have no opinion (sensus), to utter what has little or no meaning (sensus); all these are the marks of an unintelligent man. And sensus can also mean ‘frame of mind’. Here are four semantic pressures helping the word sensus to some meaning like ‘intelligence’ or ‘gumption’. In post-classical Latin it yields to them. We read in the Digest that neither a beast nor a madman has sensus. We also find the adjective sensatus used to mean ‘sensible, intelligent’ (classical Latin would probably have said cordatus). This development may also have been encouraged by an expression which we must now investigate.

146

IX. ‘COMMUNIS SENSUS’ AND ‘COMMON SENSE’

This has in its time borne a good many different meanings.

1. Koinos is the Greek for ‘common’, and we have already seen that sensus can be used as a translation of Greek nous. Koinos nous is defined by Epictetus thus: ‘There are some things which undistorted men perceive by the use of their common faculties. This state of affairs is called Koinos nous’ (III, vi, 8). Here we have, almost exactly, what common sense often means; the elementary mental outfit of the normal man. Communis sensus would be a very natural way of turning Koinos nous into Latin, but clear examples of communis sensus to mean intelligence are not very easy to find. This, from Phaedrus, is, I think, certain. The Fox, finding a tragic mask, remarks after sniffing and trundling it ‘What a fine physiognomy to have no brain inside it!’ The moral applies, says Phaedrus, to those people who have office and fame but no sensus communis (I, vii).

2. Distinct from this, so far as I can see, is the use of communis sensus as the name of a social virtue. Communis (open, unbarred, to be shared) can mean friendly, affable, sympathetic. Hence communis sensus is the quality of the ‘good mixer’, courtesy, clubbableness, even fellow-feeling. Quintilian says it is better to send a boy to school than to have a private tutor for him at home; for if he is kept away from the herd (congressus) how will he ever learn that sensus which we call communis? (I, ii, 20). On the lowest level it means tact. In Horace the man who talks to you when you obviously don’t want to talk lacks 147 communis sensus.[259] To say ‘lacks common sense’ would be a mistranslation. But the fact that the mistake is so tempting and the alteration so comparatively slight shows that these two semantic regions have at least a strip of common frontier. In that way even this usage may have made some small contribution to the later meaning.

3. Quite distinct from these is communis sensus or ‘common wit’ as a technical term in medieval psychology; originally, I presume, a rendering of Greek Koine aisthesis.[260] The old psychologists gave man five ‘outward’, and five ‘inward’, wits (or senses). The five outward wits are what we call the five senses to-day. Sometimes they are called simply the senses, and the five inward ones are called simply the wits; hence in Shakespeare ‘my five wits nor my five senses’.[261] Which five you lose, or whether you lose all ten, when you are frightened ‘out of your wits’ or ‘out of your senses’, I don’t know; probably the inward ones.

The five inward wits were originally memory, estimation, fancy, imagination, and common wit (or common sense). By Burton’s time the list has been reduced to three,[262] but common sense is still one of them, and his account of it will serve our turn; it is ‘the judge or moderator of the rest . . . by whom we discern all differences of objects; for by mine eye I do not know that I see, or by mine ear that I hear, but by common sense, who judgeth of sounds and colours: they [sc. the eye and ear] are but the organs to bring the species (appearances, 148 sense-data) to be censured (judged)’. It is in fact something like apperception; it turns mere sensation into coherent experience. We see its function in the 1590 Arcadia (III, xviii, 9) when Sidney explains how two combatants could go on fighting despite their severe wounds—‘Wrath and Courage barring the common sense from bringing any message of their case to the minde’.

It will be noticed that a man in whom the common sense or wit is suspended is not entirely in his right mind. One in whom it was permanently lacking would be an imbecile. Here we have yet another semantic pressure which could help common sense towards the meaning ‘gumption’.

4. Sensus, as we have seen, means all the erlebt; our experience, emotions, thoughts, apprehensions, and opinions. The communis sensus of mankind is what all men have ‘been through’ (e.g. pain and pleasure), or feel emotionally (fears and hopes), or think (that half a loaf’s better than no bread) or have some apprehension of (the comic, the praiseworthy), or agree to be true (that two and two make four).

Now the word communis is here ambivalent.

(a) It may contrast the sensus of the human race in general, unfavourably, with what experts think and know or what choicer spirits apprehend and feel. Common, taken that way, is ‘common or garden’, nothing above the ordinary; if you like, vulgar.

Thus Cicero says that in all arts except one (oratory) that is best which is furthest from the sensus of the ignorant; but in public speaking you have to stick to the 149 common mode of speech and the custom of the communis sensus.[263] You are not addressing men of learning or fine feeling; you can use only what will ‘find an echo in every bosom’. In Love’s Labour’s Lost the ‘godlike recompense’ of study or learning is to know ‘things hid and barr’d from common sense’ (I, i, 55-7), things beyond the thought and apprehension of ordinary men. When Spenser says that the pains of lovers seem ‘’gainst common sense, to them most sweete’[264] he does not mean, as we should if we used the same words, that the lovers are fools who like their pains contrary to all reason. He means that the gentle heart finds somehow sweet what the ‘swainish and ungentle breast’ with its merely ‘common’ apprehension would find simply disagreeable.

(b) But common may also contrast the sensus of humanity in general, favourably, with what is thought or felt by the irrational, the depraved, the sub-human. Common, so taken, has no association with vulgar. It is the quod semper, quod ubique, the normal and indeed the norm.

It is this, though he happens not to use the words common sense, that Hooker is thinking of when he says that ‘the general and perpetual voice of man is as the sentence of God himself’ (I, viii, 3). So is Cicero, when he says that some principle is vouched for ‘by truth and the nature of things and the sensus of every man’.[265] Seneca is particularly illuminating. He first produces philosophical authority to show that the wise man is self-sufficient. But then he confirms it[266] from a passage out of 150 a comic poet in order to show that these sensus (plural) are communes, are ‘universal convictions’. The ‘common sense’ or vote or sentence of humanity is august enough to confirm even the teachings of the Stoics. St Augustine speaks of people ‘divorced by some madness from the communis sensus of man’.[267] Centuries later the Jesuit Mariana writes that communis sensus ‘is, as it were, the voice of Nature whereby we may discern good from evil’.[268]

Thus the ambivalence of the word common brings it about that one’s sense may be disparaged by that adjective; but equally, one’s sense may be all the better for its commonness’. But it is time to return to the B-branch.

X. ‘SENSUS’ AND ‘SENSE (B)’

1. Sensus is the sensory awareness of anything. ‘If’, says Cicero, ‘an organism admits the sensus of pleasure, it also admits that of pain.’[269] So in English: ‘then first with fear surpris’d and sense of pain’.[270]

2. A faculty of sensory perception, one of the five senses or outward wits. ‘Every organism has sensus [plural]’, says Cicero in the place I have just quoted. What before fruition pleased the lovers in all ways, afterwards ‘takes [charms] but one sense’, said Donne.[271] In English there is (or perhaps was) a common use of the singular sense, collectively, to mean all the senses, the whole life of what medieval psychologists called the sensitive (as distinct from the vegetable or rational) soul. This appears in Donne’s reference to ‘dull sublunary 151 lovers, love Whose soul is sense’,[272] or Tennyson’s ‘sense at war with soul’—that is, in older and more precise terms, the sensitive soul at war with the rational. There is little doubt that sense is being thus used collectively when Hamlet says (III, iv, 71), ‘Sense, sure you have, Else you could not have motion’. One might be momentarily tempted to take sense here for gumption or judgement; but if it meant that, only a rather strained and remote connection with motion could be made out. If, on the other hand, Hamlet means ‘You must have senses, must have a sensitive soul’, he is making a clear and simple application of the maxim, originally Aristotelian, that ‘the external senses are found in all creatures which have the power of locomotion’.[273]

(Since we have here run across the sensitive soul it may be worth noticing that its name in Middle English is sometimes ‘sensualitee’. That is why Chaucer’s Parson says that sensualitee ‘sholde have lordshipe . . . over the body of man’.[274] When our foot ‘goes to sleep’, sensualitee, the sensitive soul, has suffered a local loss of lordship over the body. Needless to say, the word, thus used, has no ethical content.)

XI. ‘SENSE’ AND ‘SENS’ IN LATER TIMES

1. The first thing to notice is the continued, and equal, vigour both of what I have called ‘the introspective’, and what I have called ‘the aesthesis’, meanings. Preserved by the insulating power of the context, they 152 flourish happily side by side without the slightest mutual contamination. Here are two lines from Pope:

What thin partitions sense from thought divide.[275]

While pure Description held the place of sense.[276]

In the first it would never have occurred to Pope, and has never occurred to any reader of Pope, to give sense any meaning but aesthesis—perception by the five outward wits. Equally, when we read sense in the second line, the idea of aesthesis never comes into our heads. This is obviously Herbert’s use (‘if all want sense’). Description fills up the void left by the lack of profundity, of pertinent comment on life, of intellectual meat. In a word, sense in the second line is almost synonymous with ‘thought’ in the first line, there contrasted with sense. The intrusion of either meaning into the wrong line would produce nonsense. No one commits it. No one needs any semantic gymnastics to avoid it. No one notices that there was anything to avoid. Both meanings are ‘handed to us on a plate’, as separate as if they were accidental homophones.

2. In earlier sections of the chapter we have seen sense signifying thought, awareness, meaning, depth of meaning, apprehension, and (in Late Latin) intelligence. We have seen common sense signifying apperception, and then the convictions common to all undepraved or normal men. As Epictetus was pretty well known (he is one of Pepys’s favourites) his koinos nous had probably gone into the pot too. All these, simmering together, finally give the meaning gumption. For there is no need to distinguish 153 sens from le bon sens or le sens commun, nor sense from ‘good sense’ and ‘common sense’. Whatever the idea (or ideas) of a common sense contributed to the final flavour of the brew, it is now indistinguishable. Thus Descartes opens his Discourse on Method with a definition of le bon sens ou la raison; but by the second paragraph it has changed into la raison ou le sens. Descartes does not notice the change. With or without bon, sens is a synonym for raison.

3. An unexpected phenomenon now meets us. The passages quoted above from Seneca, Mariana, and Hooker make the common sense of mankind something very august. It is the voice of Nature, or even ‘is as the sentence of God himself’. Lay beside these Descartes’ statement that le (bon) sens is pretty equally bestowed on all men by nature; or Locke’s ‘He would be thought void of common sense who asked . . . why it is impossible for the same thing to be and not to be’.[277] What has happened? There is no logical contradiction. But there is a change of atmosphere; the temperature has dropped. There are causes behind this which I cannot here properly develop; a weakening in the Renaissance conception of the dignity of Man, and a growing tendency to assign moral premisses to some faculty other than reason, so that reason (or sense) is now concerned only with truth, not also with good. But the ambivalence of common has also been at work. This permits what may be called either a maximising or a minimising view of that sense (or reason) which is common to all men. On the one hand, because it is universal, cutting across all frontiers and surviving in all 154 epochs, it may be reverenced. On the other, if it is as common as that—like having two legs or a nose in your face—it can’t be anything very wonderful. To fall below it may be idiocy; to come up to it can’t possibly be a ground for self-congratulation. Locke’s words bring this out; a man doesn’t plume himself on grasping the principle that two contraries can’t both be true.

Now the curious thing is that the age which of all others made sense or good sense or common sense its shibboleth, is also the age which invariably approached it in this minimising spirit. For Locke, as we have seen, it is merely the opposite of imbecility. When Boileau says that the works of Scudéri are formed en dépit du bon sens,[278] or that il faut, mesme en chansons, du bon sens,[279] he means mere ‘reasonableness’. ‘A general trader of good sense is pleasanter company than a good scholar,’ says Addison.[280] Something homely and unspectacular is suggested. ‘If we suppose him vexed’, says Johnson, ‘it would be hard to deny him sense enough to conceal his uneasiness.’[281] All that was needed was the most elementary prudence; not to be a fool. Pope says

But, as the slightest sketch, if justly traced,

Is by ill colouring but the more disgraced,

So by false learning is good sense defaced.[282]

Sense is a ‘slight sketch’. It may be spoiled by false learning, but it will need a lot done to it before it becomes wit or wisdom.

155

At first it seems strange that the age which so constantly demanded sense should never speak of it with enthusiastic admiration. But presently one sees. The word has stooped to conquer. The implication of the whole Augustan attitude is ‘We’re not asking much. We’re not asking that poets should be learned, or that divines should be saints, or courtiers heroes, or that statesmen should bring in a heaven on earth. Our fathers tried that, and look what came of it. We ask only for rationality. A good many who tried to go beyond it never got as far. They became Enthusiasts. We are more modest. We ask for plain sense, but that we do insist on.’ The implication that if we really aim at this plain sense most of us will find that we have quite enough to do—for le sens commun (whoever said it first) n’est pas si commun—is never far below the surface. The demands of Augustanism (in reality, pretty exacting) are made to seem more obligatory by their apparent modesty. The less grandiose the name you give to your favourite virtue, the more you disgrace those who fail to practise it; they can’t do ‘even that’.

There is possibly a parallel to this in the (now perhaps obsolescent) use of decent and decency with reference to conduct which the speaker believed to be, and which perhaps was, altruistic, generous, or even heroic. Was there a double implication? (a) The standards in our class and nation are so high that what would elsewhere be praised as splendid ranks among us as ‘merely’ decent, or ‘common’ decency. (b) This behaviour is so completely obligatory that if you fail in it we must class you with people who spit in the dining-room.

156

4. What are we to make of Roscommon’s statement (he is advising us not to use ‘immodest words’) that ‘want of Decency is want of Sense’?[283] A great many immodest words have plenty of sense (meaning) and most of them refer us to objects of sense (aesthesis). Some fairly vague idea of sense as judgement was probably in his mind. But I suspect that we here see the injuries the word has undergone by becoming the popular vogue-word; and that Roscommon, wishing strongly to censure obscenity, calls it ‘lack of sense’ chiefly because sense is the favourite term of eulogy and ‘lack’ of it therefore the strongest accusation. His usage is in fact mainly tactical. Just so one can imagine one of the ‘weaker brethren’ today saying that a man or a book lacked ‘percipience’ or ‘integration’, not because at that moment (or ever) he had a very clear notion what he meant by the words, but because, from going to many sherry parties and reading many reviews, he had discovered they meant something everybody ought to have.

XII. ‘SENSIBLE’ AND ‘SENSIBILITY’

As with the verb amare we have the adjective amabilis (lovable, capable of being loved), so of course with sentire we have sensibilis. Perhaps its most usual meaning is ‘apprehensible by the senses’; thus in Seneca ‘Those who give pleasure the highest place regard the good as something apprehensible by the senses (sensibile); we, on the other hand, as something apprehensible by the intellect (intelligibile)’.[284] This of course descends into 157 English: ‘Heat, Cold, Soft, Hard, Bitter, Sweet, and all those which we call sensible qualities’.[285] That comes from what we have called in section IV the B-meaning of sentire. But English sensible sometimes derives from sentire (A). It then means ‘capable of being emotionally experienced’—usually strengthened by some word like very; as when Shakespeare’s Lucrece complains that her husband’s ‘passion’ makes her own woe ‘too sensible’.[286]

But Latin adjectives of this type were subject to a peculiar semantic infirmity. One would expect penetrabilis to mean ‘penetrable, able to be pierced’. And so it does; Ovid can speak of a body penetrable by no dart, nullo penetrabile telo.[287] But it can also mean ‘penetrating, able to pierce’; penetrabile frigus in Virgil means the piercing cold.[288] Similarly one would expect comfortabilis and its derivatives to mean ‘capable of being strengthened’; but comfortable, when the Prayer Book speaks of ‘the most comfortable sacrament’ means ‘able to strengthen, strength-giving’. Conversely unexpressive in Lycidas (l. 176) means inexpressible. Sensibilis, by the same law, besides meaning ‘apprehensible’ (by the senses or otherwise) can mean ‘able to feel, able to be aware’. Thus in Lactantius’ Divine Institutions the creation of man is described in the words ‘Then God made for Himself a sentient (sensibile) and intelligent image’ (II, xi).

This is exactly the meaning of sensible when in the Midsummer Night’s Dream, hearing the wall cursed by Pyramus and Thisbe, Theseus says ‘The wall, methinks, 158 being sensible, should curse again’ (V, i, 181); or when Hooker writes ‘Beasts are in sensible capacity as ripe even as men themselves’ (I, vi, 2), they see, smell and feel at least as well as we do.

Sometimes we may doubt whether sensible is intended to mean ‘able to feel’ or ‘able to be felt’. When Claudio in Measure for Measure (III, i, 120) speaks of ‘this sensible, warm motion’, does he mean that organic movement in him which can be felt, or that movement of nerves and brains whereby he is capable of feeling other things? When Milton’s Mammon hopefully suggests that habituation to the climate of Hell will in due course ‘remove the sensible of pain’,[289] will it remove that within him and the other fiends which is capable of feeling pain or that in the pain which is perceptible? (In the facts, no doubt, there would be no difference between these two alternatives; linguistically, I think there is.)

From the meaning ‘able to feel’, sensible proceeds to that of ‘actually feeling’, as in Johnson’s ‘I am not wholly insensible of the provocations’.[290] There is often an overcharge of meaning so that the word signifies ‘fully, or vividly, or excessively, aware of’. This may be present in the example I have just quoted. When Dalila exhorts Samson with the words ‘What remains past cure Bear not too sensibly’,[291] she certainly means ‘Let your consciousness of it be as little acute, as unemphatic, as possible’. But the idea of a superfluity to be avoided is of course partly contributed by the too. In the following from Dryden, however, though too is present, it qualifies not 159 sensible but the succeeding words: ‘The gloomy sire, too sensible of wrong to vent his rage in words’,[292] so that sensible of must mean ‘deeply or violently responsive to’. So too in Tom Jones (V, vi) ‘His backwardness . . . and his silence . . . wrought violently on her sensible and tender heart’. A modern would have used ‘sensitive’.

The state of being (with whatever meaning) sensible is of course sensibility (with the corresponding meaning). Hence in scientific or philosophical texts sensibility is sentience; the opposite of that insensibility in which, say, a faint or an anaesthetic may plunge us. The popular and colloquial use is of more interest.

Sensibility, so used, always means a more than ordinary degree of responsiveness or reaction; whether this is regarded with approval (as a sort of fineness) or with disapproval (as excess). Addison approvingly defines modesty as a ‘quick and delicate feeling’ in the soul, ‘such an exquisite sensibility as warns her to shun the first appearance of anything which is hurtful’.[293] Burke, while maintaining that ‘a rectitude of judgment in the arts does in a great measure depend upon sensibility’, warns us that ‘a good judgment does not necessarily arise from a quick sensibility of pleasure’.[294] Johnson speaks of it a little contemptuously but shows in doing so that it began to be generally admired: ‘the ambition of superior sensibility and superior eloquence dispose the lovers of arts to receive rapture at one time and communicate it at another’.[295]

The more than normal responsiveness which sensibility 160 connotes need not be responsiveness to beauty. Often it is tenderness towards the sufferings of others, so that it covers most of what would once have been described as pity or even charity. The important difference is that the idea of a merely temperamental vulnerability has replaced that of a habit in the will, achieved by practice and under Grace, as the thing admired in the merciful. ‘Dear Sensibility,’ exclaims Sterne, ‘Sensorium of the world’, and cites as an instance of it a peasant whose ‘gentle heart bleeds’ at the sight of an injured lamb.[296] Cowper writes lines ‘Addressed to Miss ——’ which combat Mrs Greville’s Prayer for Indifference. Heaven has decreed that all our ‘true delights’ should ‘flow from sympathy’. He prays to be granted, as long as he lives, ‘sweet sensibility’. I think vulnerability to pity is still the main idea. But in Mrs Radcliffe sensibility perhaps implies a more universal morbidezza, though pity still makes an important part of it. Her heroine had ‘uncommon delicacy of mind, warm affections, and ready benevolence; but with these was observable a degree of susceptibility too exquisite to admit of lasting peace. As she advanced in youth this sensibility gave a pensive tone to her spirits and a softness to her manner, which added grace to beauty and rendered her a very interesting object to persons of a congenial disposition’.[297]

The admired quality could not be better described. Mrs Radcliffe still remembers that it can be regarded as an excess (are not the virtues of Fielding’s heroes ‘the vices 161 of really good men’?) and mentions it with a pretty pretence of censure—‘too exquisite for lasting peace’. It is the very tone in which people ostensibly confess what they actually boast (‘I know it’s very silly of me but I can’t bear to see anything suffer’). Notice too that the pains inflicted on the young lady by her sensibility are amply recompensed by the fact that they make her ‘a very interesting object’. But not to everyone. Only to the only people she would want to attract, ‘persons of a congenial disposition’. For of course she would not have wished, any more than Marianne Dashwood, to interest a Colonel Brandon.

XIII. ‘SENSIBLE (D.S.)’

When sense (gumption, reasonableness) becomes the quality universally demanded, the need for an adjective to describe those who have it will inevitably be felt. On etymological and logical grounds sensate had the strongest claims to this post. But the language rejected it. Perhaps it sounded too technical and scholastic. Sensible, despite the meanings it already had, was given this new one. Thus it acquires its dangerous sense: ‘having ordinary intelligence, the opposite of silly or foolish’. It is in some ways a strange usage. To call a man sensible because he has sense is at first sight as odd as to call him ‘memorable’ because he has memory or ‘regrettable’ because he feels regret. (A ‘barkable dog’, I am told, occurs in legal language.) Perhaps this is why Johnson, who seems freely to have used sensible (d.s.) in conversation, stigmatises it as ‘merely colloquial’ in the Dictionary.

162

How long before his time sensible (d.s.) had been in use is not easy to determine. Some think they find it when Falstaff says to the Chief Justice, ‘For the box of the ear that the prince gave you, he gave it like a rude prince, and you took it like a sensible lord’.[298] But there are surely great difficulties in taking sensible here to mean prudent or intelligent. For one thing, rudeness and good sense are a strange antithesis. For another, the Chief Justice (as Shakespeare well knew from Holinshed) had reacted to his box on the ear by sending the Prince to jail. And neither the Chief Justice himself nor anyone else thought this a prudent thing to do.[299] Two other meanings for ‘sensible lord’ both seem to me to fit the context better. It might mean sensitive, thin-skinned, over-susceptible. Falstaff may, probably would, take the view that a mere Chief Justice, insulted by royalty, would have been wise to pocket the insult. He may be saying in effect ‘You made far too much fuss, stood excessively on your dignity’. This will give us a sort of antithesis to ‘rude’. What it was admittedly rowdy and ‘boisteous’ of the Prince to do, it was none the less over nice, over refined, of the Justice to resent. Alternatively, sensible could mean perceptible, noticeable, palpable. On that view ‘like a sensible lord’ would mean ‘very (excessively) perceptibly a lord’; that is, ‘making your status as a lord too noticeable’, ‘flinging your official weight about’. The Justice’s action had been, in Falstaff’s opinion, too (and too blatantly) lordly. A different Shakespearian passage is much stronger evidence for the existence of the dangerous sense in his 163 time. When Ford calls Pistol ‘a good sensible fellow’ I think he means he is no fool.[300]

XIV. TRIUMPH OF ‘SENSIBLE (D.S.)’

Whatever the early history may have been, sensible, by the time we reach the late eighteenth century, is overburdened with meanings. It can mean (1) perceptible to the senses, (2) sentient, not unconscious, (3) having such sensibility as Marianne Dashwood’s, or (4) having (good or common) sense, being no fool.

The first two of these, being scientific and philosophical, can live safely with each other and with the remaining two; with each other, because the sort of writers who use them will know precisely what they mean and make it clear to their readers, and with the other two because these seldom compete with them by entering the same contexts. But the third and fourth meanings have every chance of being used by the same speakers in the same conversation. Johnson in his Club and Mrs Thrale at her tea table will both want to talk about people who have sense and also about people who suffer from or enjoy ‘sweet sensibility’. But sensible is now the adjective for both. This is a semantic situation which is almost bound to end by destroying one or other of the two meanings.

Fortunately for the language the possible confusion was one that could not (as confusion between different senses of nature or simple can) long escape notice. It was revealed by the obvious fact that those who qualify for the 164 adjective sensible in the one sense seldom do so in the other. It would be hard to maintain that Sophia, by being ‘sensible and tender’ where Tom Jones was concerned, showed her good sense. Indeed the two classes of ‘sensible’ people designated by the two meanings of the word hardly overlap at all. The paradox, unlike many similar semantic paradoxes, is felt because all three words (sense, sensible and sensibility) are fully alive. The awareness of it, embodied in the half-punning antithesis of sense and sensibility has been preserved in the title of Jane Austen’s novel.

The upshot of the whole affair was that, for nearly all purposes, the dangerous sense achieved undisputed possession of the word sensible. Once, Marianne Dashwood and her sister would have had equal, though quite different, claims to it; it now belongs solely to people like Elinor. The settlement was a good one. Sensible (d.s.) was needed, and we have replaced sensible in its other meaning. People of sensibility are now sensitive or percipient when we approve them, sentimental or gushing when we do not. All has been for the best.

165

7
SIMPLE

It has been the curious fate of this word to achieve enormous popularity (now, I think, on the decline) without acquiring a dangerous sense. In many people’s usage it has, indeed, rather an atmosphere than anything that can be called a meaning.

We must start of course with Latin simplex; its first element related to semel (once) and its second to plicare (to fold). Originally, we must suppose, a thing was simplex when it was like a sheet of paper. Fold the sheet in two and it becomes duplex. We had a word somewhat like it in Anglo-Saxon; anfeald, as you might say, ‘onefold’. ‘You’ve heard my anfeald thought’, says someone in Beowulf (l. 256); the single, uncomplicated, unqualified, unambiguous thing I have to say. He is poising a spear in his hand while he speaks (l. 235) and is explaining to some strangers that they’d better—and the sooner the better (l. 256)—explain who they are before they go a step further. You couldn’t have a more ‘one-fold’ thought. The word appears again (afaild) in Gavin Douglas, there applied to God.[301] But we have lost it. And the (presumably) original idea of folding in the Latin word has no influence on the meanings we shall have to consider.

1. The simplex is the opposite of the compound or composite: ‘The nature of the animating principle’, says 166 Cicero, ‘must either be simplex . . . or else compounded (concreta) of diverse natures’.[302] Just so in English. ‘A foote of two sillables is either simple or mixt’, says William Webbe.[303] Locke tells us ‘one thing is to be observed concerning ideas . . . that some are simple and some complex’.[304]

2. Every compound, or so we hope, can in principle be resolved into simple ingredients, ingredients which are internally homogeneous. And as the compound is a compound, so these ultimate ingredients are simples. Thus in older medical language the ultimate herbal ingredients of a medicine are simples, and a medicine which consists of one single herb (or what not) is a simple. Thus Amarillis in The Faithful Shepherdess (II, iii, 72) speaks of ‘all simples good for medicine’. We had a verb from this once. To go looking for such ingredients was to simple. ‘I know most of the plants of my country,’ says Browne, ‘yet methinks I do not know so many as when I . . . had scarcely ever simpled further than Cheap-side.’[305]

3. Anything that is not added to, anything operating by itself, is simple. In this sense the word is almost synonymous with ‘mere’. In All’s Well we read of a remedy ‘whose simple touch Is powerful to araise King Pepin’ (II, i, 78). Its mere touch; nothing more is needed. We get the same in French: ‘En la justice . . . tout ce qui est au delà de la mort simple, me semble pure cruauté’; mere death, not aggravated by tortures.[306] Examples of this 167 usage are no doubt plentiful in Latin and in all languages that owe it the word, but they are not easy to identify. So often other ideas may come in as well. The sort of difficulty I have in mind can be shown by a glance at Pope’s Essay on Man I, 103 f.—the Poor Indian passage. ‘Proud science’ has never taught his soul this or that but ‘simple nature’ has given him the hope of immortality. Does this mean ‘mere’ nature, nature unaided, or does it mean ‘Nature, who (as we all know) is unsophisticated, free from artificiality’?

So far all has been plain enough. But we must now divide. This semantic trunk throws out three branches of meaning, which may be distinguished as the logical, the ethical, and the popular.

I. THE LOGICAL BRANCH

Simply, and Latin simpliciter, take over the function of the Greek adverb haplôs. What that function was, a good formal logician would define for us accurately in a very few words, but readers who are not themselves formal logicians might not be greatly enlightened. We had better take the slower way of learning its meaning from live examples.[307] They are all from Aristotle’s Ethics.

‘The best critic in each subject is the man educated in that subject; but the best critic haplôs is the [generally] educated man’ (1094 b).

‘If one pursues B for the sake of A, he pursues A in 168 itself, but B incidentally. To pursue anything “in itself” means the same as to pursue it haplôs’ (1151 b).

‘Some define the virtues as absences of passion or states of tranquillity. But this is wrong. For they say this haplôs, without the necessary addenda such as “in the right way” or “on the right occasion”’ (1104b).

‘Things which are always good haplôs but not always good for a particular person’ (1129b).

‘That habit of the soul which, haplôs, is virtue, when exercised towards our neighbour is “justice”’ (1130a).

‘A similar problem arises about jettison, when men throw goods overboard in a storm to lighten ship. This act would not be voluntary haplôs, though any man in his senses would do it to save himself and his shipmates. Such acts are, then, mixed. They are voluntary [in the circumstances] but perhaps involuntary haplôs’ (1110a).

The use of simpliciter to translate haplôs is conveniently illustrated by Aquinas when he is discussing the same problem, and arrives at a different conclusion. Such acts are ‘voluntary simpliciter, but involuntary secundum quid’.[308]

For purely logical purposes it is best to use in English the Latin word. For our own purpose, the meaning of it, and of haplôs, is now, I hope tolerably clear. What is good or true (or anything else) haplôs is so ‘in itself’, intrinsically, unconditionally, not in relation to special circumstances; can be called good or true (or whatever) without qualification. The opposites of haplôs would be expressed by reservations: ‘in a way’, ‘in a sense’, ‘for some people’, ‘under certain conditions’, ‘up to a point’, ‘with 169 the necessary qualifications’, ‘relatively’, ‘in the circumstances’.

Our older writers use simply in precisely this way. As in Hooker’s ‘under man no creature is capable of felicity and bliss . . . because their chiefest perfection consisteth in that which is best for them, but not in that which is simply best, as ours doth’ (I, xi, 3). For our good is God, who is best simpliciter. A bone is a good for a dog but a bone is not good simply. (While it was still in a live animal the bone was a good for that animal, and there might come a day when it was a good for a palaeontologist. But never good simply.)

‘Other retentions and evacuations there are, not simply necessary but at some times’, says Burton (I, ii, 2, 4).

The words which I have italicised in the following (from Taylor) perhaps show that in his time the logical use of simply was already becoming a little less familiar. He seems to feel it needs expansion: ‘Elias, that he might bring the people from idolatry, caused a sacrifice to Baal to be made . . . which of itself was simply and absolutely evil’.[309] The word ‘considered’ in Johnson’s (Boswell, 12 June 1784) ‘If you admit any degree of punishment, there is an end of your argument from infinite goodness simply considered’, may have the same cause.

Now to say that a thing is simply good (like charity) and not merely good for someone (like insulin for diabetics), or that it is simply bad (like envy) and not merely bad under certain conditions (as eight is a bad hour for breakfast if you’re catching a train at 8.15) is to 170 say more about the thing—to exalt it higher or damn it deeper—than we should do if we admitted qualifications. Hence, by a degradation of the logical use, simply and absolutely (which we have already seen Taylor using to explicate simply) become merely intensifying adverbs. By prefixing them to an adjective ordinary speakers will soon feel that they are merely underlining the adjective or asserting a strong claim to it. Hence, in our own day, ‘simply delicious’, ‘simply marvellous’, ‘absolutely frightful’. (One could even have, though I am not sure I have yet heard it, ‘it’s all absolutely relative’.) This is a kind of gush which many suppose to be specifically modern, but it was already beginning in the sixteenth century. ‘He hath simply the best wit of any handy craft man in Athens’, says someone in Midsummer Night’s Dream (IV, ii, 9); and Sir Andrew claims to ‘have the back-trick simply as strong as any man in Illyria’.[310] Thus we may—in such studies as this we must—trace the noble dust of Alexander stopping a bung-hole and see how a homespun’s schwärmerei or a gull’s vanity makes its own momentary use of tools inherited from the great masters of all occidental thought.

II. THE ETHICAL BRANCH

Simplicity here is the opposite of duplicity. A man is simplex when there is ‘only one of him’ in the sense that the character he shows you and that which he bears within are one not two; especially, of course, when his words and his thought, his professed and his real motives, are 171 identical. ‘You and I are speaking to-day simplicissime’, says someone in Tacitus[311]—frankly, sincerely, as we really think and feel. With an immeasurable deepening the idea can then be internalised so that it refers to an inner singleness or simplicity which makes a man sincere with himself, seeing what he sees and playing no tricks with his own knowledge or purpose. ‘If your eye is haplous’, says the Greek—haplous being of course the adjective of the adverb haplôs;[312], and the Vulgate, si oculus tuus fuerit simplex (A.V. ‘single’).

Sincere people are guileless, and those who have no guile themselves are not quick to suspect it in others. (It has been said that no one ever meets anyone but himself.) It is here that the degradation of simplex begins. To be guileless, unsuspicious—is it not next door to being credulous, gullible? Accordingly Apuleius, explaining why Psyche believed the cock-and-bull story of her jealous sisters, says ‘she was seized by the terror of such alarming words, for poor little (misella) Psyche was simplex and of a tender wit, animi tenella’.[313] An Elizabethan would here have rendered simplex by ‘seelie’. Apuleius does not yet mean quite silly in the modern sense, but he certainly means she was no Solomon. Ingenuous Psyche? Naïve Psyche? At any rate, a Psyche quite incapable of looking after herself, anyone’s prey.

The simple, being guileless and credulous, are of course not dangerous. They are harmless or—notice how all these words have a flavour of patronage or disparagement—‘innocuous’. The apostles are told in St Matthew (x. 16) 172 to be as akeraioi as doves. The word, so far as I can make out, meant ‘guileless’, and the Vulgate’s simplices would be a good translation. Tyndale, Cranmer, and Geneva render it ‘innocent’, and A.V., ‘harmless’; presumably, for them, synonymous with simple. And the idea of harmlessness is probably uppermost when Fraunchise in the Romance of the Rose is said (l. 1198) to be ‘simple come uns colons’ (English version, ‘simple as dowve on tree’, l. 1219).

But in the same poem we can find the word at a further stage of its decline. Frend is advising the lover to ignore infidelities in his mistress; even when they are flagrant he should pretend that he is blind or plus simples que n’est uns bugles (l. 9700)—pretend, in fact, that he has no more sense than a buffalo. Simples has got beyond the senses ‘credulous’ or ‘naïf’; it means downright stupid. It is not far from this when Claudius accuses Hamlet of ‘An understanding simple and unschooled’ (I, ii, 97) or when, centuries later Mrs Morland says ‘You are fretting over General Tilney and that is very simple of you’.[314] Often the defect implied is one of learning, skill and subtlety—a defect felt to be rather charming and put forward as a claim for pity, as in Henry VIII, ‘I am a simple woman much too weak To oppose your cunning’ (II, iv, 106). So Desdemona asks the Duke ‘let me find a charter in your voice to assist my simpleness’.[315]

The word takes a much sharper downward turn in the sense which has given us simpleton. Simple can still—in Ireland anyway—mean ‘mentally deficient’. In Grimstone’s 173 Siege of Ostend (1604) we read of one who was ‘lame of his body and half simple’—half an imbecile. When the exasperated Friar in Romeo asks ‘what simpleness is this?’ (III, iii, 77) simpleness probably means idiocy, and I think ‘Simple Simon’ in the Rhyme was a fatuus. Significantly ‘innocent’—and simple, as we have seen, can mean that—is used in the same way, so that there is a section in Taylor’s Worthy Communicant headed ‘Whether Innocents, Fools, and Madmen, may be admitted’.[316] For innocent, simple, silly, ingenuous, and Greek euethes, all illustrate the same thing—the remarkable tendency of adjectives which originally imputed great goodness, to become terms of disparagement. Give a good quality a name and that name will soon be the name of a defect. Pious and respectable are among the comparatively modern casualties, and sanctimonious was once a term of praise.

As far as simple is concerned, Taylor comments on the process: ‘Simplicity is grown into contempt . . . unwary fools and defenceless people were called simple.’[317] And Shakespeare exploits it to good effect in the line ‘And simple truth miscall’d simplicity’,[318] where simple, I take it, is not ‘mere’ but ‘guileless, single-minded’.

III. THE POPULAR BRANCH

We have already had simple or simplex as ‘mere’, not added to. The meaning I now want to consider is perhaps 174 just budding out of this when Horace, deprecating ‘Persian’—Thackeray took ‘Frenchified’ as our equivalent—luxury in the arrangements for a dinner, says ‘Don’t bother to add anything to the simplici myrto’, ‘the mere or plain myrtle’.[319]

The word ‘plain’, which itself well deserves study, is the best translation for simplex in this sense; ‘elaborate’ or ‘ornate’ are the opposites. Thus Milton rightly turns Horace’s simplex munditiis[320] as ‘plain in thy neatness’. (Why, in heaven’s name, did Monsignor Knox think his version of that ode was ‘modelled on the Authorised Version’?)

Examples of this sense could be had by the armful. Addison says the opening lines of Paradise Lost are ‘as plain, simple, and unadorned as any in the whole poem’.[321] Gulliver’s ‘style is very plain and simple’.[322]

This sense again divides into two.

1. What is simple or plain is the reverse of complicated. A complicated process is hard to learn and a complicated argument hard to follow. Therefore simple comes to mean ‘easy’. The idea that it is within the capacity of those who are simple (in the sense ‘unskilled’) may perhaps have helped this development.

‘God never does that by difficult ways which may be done by ways that are simple and easy’, says John Norris in his Essay towards the Theory of the Ideal World (1701). F. H. Bradley in the Preface to his Logic (1922) says ‘if I saw further I should be simpler’.

175

2. There is a general feeling that what is unelaborate is modest or unostentatious. Simple thus acquires a sense which I might find it hard enough to define if a useful piece of modern slang did not help me out; the simple is the opposite of the ‘posh’. Frugal and homely ways are simple ways; Lenten fare, simple fare. In Gawain and the Green Knight we read of ‘the crabbed Lenten That fraystes the flesch with the fysche and fode more simple’ (l. 502)—is a trial to our flesh ‘with fish and simpler diet’. Virgil speaks of one whose health was never impaired by a recherché table, non epulae nocuere repostae.[323] Dryden renders it ‘simple his beverage, homely was his food’.

In this usage, which is still very current, we often have good examples of the insulating power of the context. When we are warned that we shall get only ‘a very simple meal’ we may expect a shepherd’s pie or a dish of hash. These are certainly not simpler than a pheasant or a haunch of venison in the sense of being less complicated, containing fewer heterogeneous elements. And to cook these well is not a simpler (in the sense ‘easier’) operation. Indeed it is everyone’s experience that when we are hard up and start economising, our lives become simpler in the sense that they become homelier and less ‘posh’ while at the same time they become less simple (more complicated). Rags tacked together, and braces supplemented with string, and sleeves where you can hardly find the fairway—torn linings leading to so many dead-ends—make a man’s toilet marvellously complicated.

176

But simple as the opposite of ‘posh’, elaborate, or ostentatious, bifurcates again. It can be either derogatory or laudatory.

In its derogatory use it means, in one sense of that word, ‘poor’; ‘not up to much’, second-rate, trumpery, slight. Thus, again from Gawain: ‘Now forsake ye this silke, sayde the burde thenne, For hit is simple in hitself?’ (l. 1846)—because it doesn’t look much of a thing? Of course this is mock modesty, quite apart from its magical properties it was far from simple. But the lady uses the language of real modesty. So in Malory we learn that knights who use paramours will be unlucky and ‘shal be overcome with a simpler knight than they be hemself’ (VI, x)—a knight whose form or skill is below their own. In the same text (II, v) ‘your quarrel is ful simple’ might mean that it is foolish; more probably, I think, that it is trivial. Finally, simple can mean low-born, not of the gentry; as when the old fisherman says in Waverley (ch. XXXII) ‘gentle or simple shall not darken my door’.

As a term of praise it covers several shades of meaning. When Shame in the Romance of the Rose (1. 3563) si fu umeliant e simple, the English version gives ‘Humble of hir porte and made it simple’ (l. 3863); simple is almost exactly a synonym for ‘humble’. In Zechariah ix. 9, where A.V. reads ‘lowly’, Coverdale had ‘lowly and simple’, a doublet of synonyms. So in the Romance where we are told that Beauty was simple comme une esposee (l. 1000), ‘simple as byrde in bour’,[324] something 177 like ‘modest’ or ‘bashful’ might do. And so also for Chaucer’s Prioress who ‘of her smiling was ful simple and coy’ (A. 119), demure, unobtrusive. Coy, ultimately from quietus, is not far removed from it in meaning. Both adjectives paint a character who was far from being ‘loud’.

IV. THE SEMANTIC SEDIMENT

The logical branch of this word’s meanings has little effect on the others. But nearly all those others are bound together and (as Donne might say) ‘interinanimate’ one another in an unusual way, so that it is often impossible to decide which is intended or, if there are many intended, which is uppermost.

Dante writes: ‘From the hand of Him who loves her before she is, like a young girl who prattles, with laughter and tears, forth comes l’anima semplicetta.’[325] We notice that Dante is using a diminutive. The feeling which prompted Apuleius to his misella and tenella for ‘simple Psyche’ is at work. The new-created anima or psyche is a touching or disarming thing, viewed with tenderness and not without pity. But if we try to go beyond the emotional content of the word, I do not know what definable sense we could fix upon it. Is the soul simple because she is uncomplicated? or innocent? or gullible? or unskilled? or humble? or foolish? or for all these reasons? Could Dante himself have told us?

Simple, as we have seen, can impute either defects (lack of intelligence, of rationality even, of skill, of nobility) or virtues (sincerity, humility). But none of these defects is 178 such as to produce hatred. Good reason why; they leave our self-love secure. We feel superior when we impute them. Even if they irritate us, there is some pity, often some amusement and indulgence, mixed with our irritation. The idiot (one thing that simple can mean) may indeed raise uneasiness or disgust in a modern; but he does not seem to have done so in our ancestors. They loved ‘fools’ and kept them as pets. Again, the simple are the harmless; we feel safe in their presence as well as superior. But, oddly enough, the virtues which this word can impute have the same effect. Humility disarms us, and we seldom acknowledge a man’s moral superiority to us in guilelessness and truth without reimbursing our self-esteem by a feeling that we are at least equally superior to him in acuteness and knowledge of the world. (The humour of Chesterton’s Father Brown stories depends on the continual pricking of this bubble.) Hence, over a very wide range of its senses, simple either imputes virtues and defects which can equally be contemplated de haut en bas, or else, when the speaker uses it of himself (more often perhaps herself) is placatory—claims our indulgence, deprecates our severity, and flatters us a little. Yes, and even while it assumes the form of self-depreciation, it gently insinuates that the thing confessed is really almost a virtue; is at least very touching and endearing. ‘I’m afraid you’ll find we live very simply’ may in fact be an appeal that we should regard dirty plates and tepid food, not as the results of laziness, but as somehow homely, unostentatious, modest, simple with the laudable simplicité des anciens mœurs.

179

This is why I describe the final state of the word as a semantic sediment. What effectively remains is not this or that precise sense but a general appealingness or disarmingness.

‘They prefer the simplicity of faith before that knowledge which, curiously sifting and disputing too boldly . . . chilleth . . . all warmth of zeal’.[326] Faith un-added to and ‘mere’? Unskilled? Easy? Humble?

‘Never anything can be amiss when simpleness and duty tender it.’[327] Sincerity? Unskilfulness? Simple as against gentle? Silliness?

‘His place of birth a solemn Angel tells to simple shepherds.’[328]

‘A general simplicity in our dress, our discourse, and our behaviour.’[329] Sincerity (not affectation)? Plainness (not ‘poshness’)? The easy (not the hard)? The modest (not the ostentatious)?

Finally, in A. C. Benson’s From a College Window: ‘Simple, silent, deferential people such as station-masters, butlers, gardeners’ (pp. 2-3). ‘Quiet lives of study and meditation led here’ (i.e. in Cambridge colleges) ‘by wise and simple men’ (pp. 8-9). ‘The University is a place where a poor man, if he be virtuous, may live a life of dignity and simplicity’ (p. 9). ‘How seldom does a perfectly simple, human relationship exist between a boy and his father’ (p. 10). ‘To have leisure and a degree of simple stateliness assured’ (p. 12). ‘I have grown to feel that the ambitions which we preach and the successes for 180 which we prepare are very often nothing but a missing of the simple road . . . I have grown to believe that the one thing worth aiming at is simplicity of heart and life’ (p. 14).

The simplicity often lacking between father and son might be sincerity, but I think Benson would have used sincerity if he meant exactly that. In what sense either butlers or fellows of colleges are usually simple is hard to say. In two of the instances the word has, I fancy, almost an exclusively placatory function. You might grudge us ‘dignity’ or ‘stateliness’; yet surely not ‘dignity and simplicity’ or ‘simple stateliness’. Yet the continual recurrence of the word is undoubtedly necessary to the tone of the whole essay.

Though I do not myself much care for this word when it is in this condition—it is a soft, frilly, pouting, question-begging, almost a sly and sneaking, word—I would not say it is now meaningless. It indicates an (emotionally) specific area; like supernatural. We cannot say it serves none of the purposes of language.

181

8
CONSCIENCE AND CONSCIOUS

I. PRELIMINARIES

Greek oida and Latin scio mean ‘I know’. The Greek verb can be compounded with the prefix sun or xun (sunoida), the Latin with cum which in composition becomes con-, giving us conscio. Sun and cum in isolation mean ‘with’. And sometimes they retain this meaning when they become prefixes, so that sunoida and conscio can mean ‘I know together with, I share (with someone) the knowledge that’. But sometimes they had a vaguely intensive force, so that the compound verbs would mean merely ‘I know well’, and perhaps finally little more than ‘I know’. Each verb has a train of related words. With sunoida goes the noun suneidesis and (its synonym) the neuter participle to suneidos, and the masculine participle suneidôs; with conscio, the noun conscientia and the adjective conscius. It will be seen at once that the double value of the prefixes may affect all these, so that suneidesis and conscientia could be either the state (or act) of sharing knowledge or else simply knowledge, awareness, apprehension—even something like mind or thought.

Our word therefore has two branches of meaning; that which uses the full sense (‘together’) of the prefix and that in which the prefix is—or may be treated for our purpose 182 as being—almost inoperative. Let us for convenience call them the together branch and the weakened branch.

The richest and most useful developments of the weakened branch are in English comparatively modern, but some of its earlier and obsolete senses need to be noticed at once. I shall therefore begin with a brief glance at the weakened branch; then turn to the together branch; and in conclusion turn back to the weakened in its later condition.

II. THE WEAKENED BRANCH

We read in Diogenes Laertius (VII, 85) ‘Chrysippus says that the first property of every animal is its structure and the suneidesis of this’. Suneidesis here can hardly mean anything other than ‘awareness’. The Greek Lexicon quotes from Plutarch ‘to suneidos of the affairs’, presumably the knowledge of them. The Septuagint version gives us ‘curse not the king in your suneidesis[330] where A.V. has ‘curse not the king, no not in thy thought’.

Latin usages of the same sort are numerous, but usually post-classical. Macrobius mentions one Vettius as ‘unice conscius of all sacred matters’—uniquely knowledgeable about or learned in.[331] Where the Septuagint has merely ‘we don’t know’ (ouk oidamen) in Genesis xliii. 22, the Vulgate reads ‘it is not in our conscientia’. When Tertullian speaks of convictions lodged in our ‘innate conscientia[332] or Lactantius of what is ‘clear to our conscientia[333] some sense like ‘mind’ or ‘understanding’ is required.

It will at once be obvious that the French la conscience 183 descends from the weakened branch; a Frenchman could perhaps use it to translate the conscientia of Tertullian and Lactantius. In Modern English the specialisation of consciousness for this purpose has left conscience free to develop almost exclusively the ‘together’ senses; a notable example of desynonymisation. But it is a comparatively recent achievement. When Gawain saw his hostess steal into his bedroom and tried to figure out ‘in his conscience’ what this might portend, the word must mean ‘mind’ or ‘thought’.[334] In Shakespeare’s ‘Canst thou the conscience lack to think I shall lack friends?’[335] it seems to mean ‘sense’ or ‘gumption’. And this meaning, though finally defeated by those of the together branch, may have had subtle effects upon its conquerors.

One late Middle English usage is hard to account for. Chaucer apostrophises Dido as the ‘sely’ (guileless) woman, full of innocence, pity, truth, and conscience.[336] His prioress sheds tears at the sight of a mouse in a trap because of her ‘conscience and tendre herte’,[337] and that whole passage is ushered in by the words ‘for to speken of her conscience’ (l. 142). In Gower, Pompey ‘tok pite with conscience’ on the captive Armenian king (VII, 3230). In all these some such meaning as ‘tenderness’ (vulnerability, even excessive sensibility) seems to be required. The influence of the ‘together’ branch may have had something to do with it. There might also be a progression from ‘awareness’ to ‘extreme awareness’, thence to ‘perceptiveness’, the opposite of callousness.

184

III. THE EXTERNAL WITNESS

To the ‘together’ branch, to usages where sun- and con- have their full meaning, I now turn.

The man who shares the knowledge of anything with So-and-so can say ‘Sunoida (or conscio) this to So-and-so’. In order to avoid many cumbrous circumlocutions I am going to describe this state of affairs as ‘consciring’. But of course when everyone is consciring about a piece of knowledge (e.g. that the Sun rises in the east) it will never be mentioned. Consciring is worth talking about only when two, or a few, men share some knowledge which most men do not possess; in fact, when they are in a secret. The man who conscires anything with me is conscius (or suneidos) to me. The fact of his consciring is his conscientia (or suneidesis), his shared knowledge.

When Teiresias tries to evade the questions put him by Oedipus about the origin of the curse that has fallen on the city, Oedipus says ‘What? suneidos (though you are in the secret) you won’t tell?’[338] In the Antigone the soldier, questioned about the burial of Polyneices, says he will take any oath that he has neither done it himself nor tô xuneidenai—been privy to, been in the confidence of, anyone who did it (l. 266). Tacitus says that Sallustius had been interficiendi Agrippae conscius, privy to, in the secret of, Agrippa’s murder;[339] or again, that when Tiberius practised astrology he ‘used the conscientia of a single freedman’, took only that one into his confidence, admitted no other witness of his proceedings.[340] By metaphor, 185 an inanimate object or an abstraction can be conscius, can have conscientia. In Ovid, Ajax, competing with Ulysses for the reward of having done best service in the Trojan War, says that his own deeds were all done in public while his rival produces ‘feats he performed without witness, feats of which only Night is conscia’—to which only Night was privy.[341]

Hobbes, in a curious passage which is perhaps not very true to the idiomatic English of his own day, gives English conscious exactly the classical meaning of conscius: ‘When two or more men know of one and the same fact [i.e. deed] they are said to be conscious of it one to another.’[342]

Since secrets often are, and are always suspected of being, guilty secrets, the normal implications of conscius and conscientia are bad. My conscius, the man who is conscius mihi, who shares my secret, who can give evidence about something I have done, is usually the fellow-conspirator; therefore the possible witness against me, the possible blackmailer, or at least the man who can taunt me with my deed and make me ashamed.

It was principally, I believe, a desire to imitate the Latin classics rather than a native English tendency that gave this sense of conscious (privy to) a great vogue in literature from the Restoration period down to the early nineteenth century. Thus in Denham the hunted stag flies through ‘the conscious groves, the scenes of his past triumphs and his loves’.[343] The usage here is of course very 186 flaccid; only the tiniest shade of mingled archness and pathos is gained by reminding us that these groves had witnessed his youthful battlings and ruttings. There is more point in Milton’s ‘So all ere day-spring under conscious night Secret they finished’.[344] What they finished—the manufacture of the first artillery—was really secret and, in Milton’s view, abominable; personified Night was privy to their crime. The most interesting and most often misunderstood examples are in Jane Austen. In Northanger Abbey (ch. XXX) Henry Tilney is introduced to Mrs Morland ‘by her conscious daughter’. She was conscious in exactly the classical sense; knowing much which her mother did not know about Henry and her own relations to him, she was in a secret, shared a knowledge with him. This is ‘being conscious’; but you can also ‘look conscious’, look like a conspirator or accomplice. Mrs Jennings is sure that Colonel Brandon’s letter had something to do with Miss Williams ‘because he looked so conscious when I mentioned her’.[345] He looked as if he had a secret on his mind. So in the same book (ch. XVIII) ‘he coloured very deeply . . . Elinor had met his eye and looked conscious likewise’. Many students whom I have asked to explain these passages were content with the theory that, somehow or other, conscious meant self-conscious’. But this seems, without further explanation, an impossible bit of semantic history. No doubt when one is conscious, when one has a secret, one tends to be, and to look, ‘self-conscious’. Thus, if you like, the speaker’s meaning is ‘self-conscious’ in the sense that the mental 187 state and facial expression she refers to would in fact be what we call ‘self-conscious’. But that is not the word’s meaning.

IV. THE INTERNAL WITNESS

Man might be defined as a reflexive animal. A person cannot help thinking and speaking of himself as, and even feeling himself to be (for certain purposes), two people, one of whom can act upon and observe the other. Thus he pities, loves, admires, hates, despises, rebukes, comforts, examines, masters or is mastered by, ‘himself’. Above all he can be to himself in the relation I have called consciring. He is privy to his own acts, is his own conscius or accomplice. And of course this shadowy inner accomplice has all the same properties as an external one; he too is a witness against you, a potential blackmailer, one who inflicts shame and fear.

Linguistically, the construction which represents this experience in the simplest form is ‘I conscire (this or that) to myself’. Thus in Aristophanes ‘xunoida, I conscire, many dreadful deeds to myself’[346]—I know a lot against myself. Or in St Paul: ‘I conscire (sunoida) nothing to myself.’[347] The A.V. rendering, ‘I know nothing by myself’, not very good even when it was made, now completely obscures the meaning. The proper translation is ‘I know nothing against myself’. In Latin it is the same. Horace says that the ‘brazen rampart’ round a happy life should be nil conscire sibi,[348] to know nothing against oneself, to have nothing ‘on one’s mind’. It will be noticed that the things conscired in the passage from 188 Aristophanes and the things of which there are none to be conscired in those from St Paul and Horace, are evil. In the situation within a man, as in the situation between man and man, consciring is presumed to be of evil unless the reverse is explicitly stated.

Now the state of thus consciring to (or with) oneself is in Greek suneidesis (or, more rarely sunesis), and in Latin of course conscientia. ‘What is your malady?’ Menelaus asks the haunted matricide Orestes. ‘Sunesis’, he replies, ‘for I have done a dreadful deed and conscire it’.[349] The Septuagint version of Wisdom reads ‘Wickedness condemned by an internal witness is a cowardly thing and expects the worst, being hard pressed by suneidesis’ (xviii. 11). Close to this is Menander’s statement that if even the toughest man is aware of guilt, sunesis makes him a very coward.[350] The same experience finds expression centuries later when the murderer in Richard III says that conscience ‘makes a man a coward’ (I, iv, 132) or Richard apostrophises ‘Coward Conscience’ (V, iii, 180). When you have a clean bill of moral health, that is, when you conscire no evil to yourself, you are eusuneidetos, have a good suneidesis.[351] So in Latin, when what you conscire to yourself is good, or when at least you conscire to yourself nothing bad, you have a ‘good’ conscientia. ‘All wish to hide their sins,’ says Seneca, ‘but a good conscientia loves the light.’[352]

One who conscires something to himself is of course conscius sibi, privy to himself, in his own secret; or 189 suneidos heautô in Greek. It would be prudish not to quote the passage, worthy of Walt Disney, where Juvenal describes the mysteries of the Bona Dea (which excluded all men) as a ceremony testiculi sibi conscius unde fugit mus (VI, 339)—whence a (male) mouse hurries away, laden with the secret of its own virility. Exactly the same construction was current in older English. ‘If he be an impudent flatterer,’ says Bacon, ‘look, wherein a man is most conscious to himself that he is most defective . . . that will the flatterer entitle him to.’[353] So in Bunyan: ‘I am conscious to myself of many failings.’ A modern reader, carelessly ignoring the to himself and to myself, will think he has met conscious (d.s.) (in its dangerous sense of ‘aware’). He will have missed a shade of the real meaning.

As I have already said, consciring, whether to oneself or to another, is usually of evil, usually conspiratorial. It may, however, be of good, as in Sophocles:[354] ‘being valiant, he is conscious (of it) to himself (hautô sunoide). When conscious or conscience are of qualities, not defects, a neglect of their precise meaning may be disastrous. Milton’s Eve drew back a little from Adam’s suit, so impelled by ‘her virtue and the conscience of her worth, That would be wooed, and not unsought be won’.[355] We rub the bloom off the passage if we give conscience simply the meaning of modern ‘consciousness’ and take Milton to be telling us simply that Eve knew she was eminently desirable. It is far more delicate than that. It is (transferred to a woman) what Sidney attributes to a heroic 190 king, the ‘secreat assurance of his owne worthines which (although it bee never so well cloathed in modestie) yet alwaies lives in the worthyest mindes’.[356] A secret assurance. You must bring in the consciring. Eve’s beauty was a secret between Eve and herself, ‘worthy of sacred silence’ even within, neither Eve mentioning to the other what both Eves could not but know, her conscientia of it thus resembling a conspiracy in all but guilt.

V. SUMMARY

This inner witness, one’s own conscientia, or privity, to oneself, is already a sufficiently formidable idea. Quintilian (V, xi) quotes as a proverb conscientia mille testes; one’s own consciring is (as bad as) a thousand (external) witnesses. But we must also notice what conscientia, in the examples hitherto quoted, is not. It bears witness to the fact, say, that we committed a murder. It does not tell us that murder is wrong; we are supposed to know that in some other way. In this respect it is exactly like an external witness who gives evidence about matter of fact; the criminality or innocence of the fact has been fixed by the legislator and will be declared by the judge. Hence according to the usages we have considered it would make no sense to say ‘My conscientia tells me this is wrong’; it tells me simply that I have done this—for of course what we conscire is always in the past. Again, conscientia, so far as we have seen, issues no commands or permissions. Those can come from the law or the bench, but not from the witness box. To talk of ‘obeying’ or ‘disobeying’ 191 your conscience, so long as that word remains in the semantic stage we have been observing, would be nonsensical. I cannot by any present action ‘obey’ my future privity to the fact of having done that action itself. Nor is there yet any idea of conscience as a separate faculty of the soul. The only faculty involved is knowing by memory. Suneidesis or conscientia is rather ‘a state of affairs’; knowing about your own past actions what others, or most others, do not know.[357]

VI. THE INTERNAL LAWGIVER

The remarkable development of meaning whereby conscience, so to speak, passed from the witness-box to the bench and even to the legislator’s throne, must now be considered. Some such process is already foreshadowed 192 in a fragment of Menander quoted by Mr Pierce:[358] ‘to all mortals suneidesis is theos’—which might be rendered ‘is a god’ or ‘is divine’, but hardly ‘is God’. More important is the influence of the New Testament.

Some of its usages quite clearly conform to the pattern we have already studied; suneidesis means consciring and sunoida means ‘I conscire’. Such are the passages from I Cor. iv. 4, noted above, ‘I conscire nothing (that is, nothing bad) to myself; ‘from a pure heart and good suneidesis’;[359] ‘a good suneidesis’;[360] ‘with all good suneidesis’.[361] But other passages are harder. ‘With suneidesis of the idol’ in I Cor. viii. 7 is possibly corrupt. There is a similar use of suneidesis with the genitive in I Pet. ii. 19, ‘It is meritorious if a man who is unjustly punished patiently bears his sufferings through suneidesis of God’. What this means, or how A.V. could get out of it ‘for conscience toward God’, I am uncertain.

I now turn to passages which may probably have contributed to the great semantic shift. In I Cor. viii. 10, St Paul says that if a ‘weak brother’, a scrupulous person, sees you eating meat which has been offered to idols—a thing, in St Paul’s view, innocent in itself—his suneidesis will be emboldened or ‘built up’ to do likewise. (This is a bad thing because, being scrupulous, he will probably be worried about it in retrospect.) What St Paul really meant is a question for theologians; we, busied about the history of a word, are concerned with what he would possibly, or probably, or almost inevitably, be taken to 193 mean by succeeding generations. I believe this passage would have suggested to them (as to most of us) the idea that suneidesis here means, not consciring, but ‘judgement as to what is right and wrong’. The weak brother’s scale of values, or standard of good and evil, originally classified the eating of sacrificed flesh as a sin; under your influence, encouraged by your example, he alters his scale or standard, modifies his moral judgement. Again, in Rom. xiii. 5, we are told to obey magistrates ‘not only because of the wrath’ (because it is dangerous not to) but also ‘because of suneidesis’ (A.V. ‘for conscience sake’). Now it may be true in fact that St Paul only meant ‘Obey, not only for safety’s sake, but also because, later on, you will not like consciring to yourself that you have not’; it being assumed that we all know we ought to be law-abiding, and that the conscience or consciring of a failure in this duty will be a ‘bad’ conscience. But the passage very easily, indeed more easily, suggests that suneidesis here means our actual moral judgement (that men should be law-abiding). Similarly in II Cor. iv. 2, ‘commending ourselves to all men’s suneidesis’ may in fact mean only ‘showing ourselves respectable to all men’s knowledge’, sun- being of the weakened branch; but it can easily be taken to mean ‘behaving in a way which everyone’s moral judgement will approve’.

Whether the word is already taking on a new meaning in the New Testament or whether a new meaning, arising from different causes, led to a misreading of these passages and was then, by that very misreading, greatly strengthened, the change was certainly effected and the 194 new sense remains current today. To trace it through the earlier Christian centuries would be beyond my learning and beyond our present needs.

In its new sense conscience is the inner lawgiver: a man’s judgement of good and evil. It speaks in the imperative, commanding and forbidding. But, as so often, the new sense does not replace the old. The old lives on and the new is added to it, so that conscience now has more than one meaning.

Theologians and scholars are aware of this and draw the necessary distinctions. Aquinas, who claims to be conforming to the ‘common use of language’, says that conscientia is an application of our knowledge to our own acts, and that this application occurs in three ways. (1) We judge that we have done this or that. (2) We judge that something ought, or ought not to be done. (3) We judge that our past act was good or bad. The first is conscire in the classical sense. The second, which really includes the third (synteresis or synderesis) is something quite different; something which will be named, according to the system we employ, practical reason, moral sense, reflection, the Categorical Imperative, or the super-ego. Conscientia in this second sense can be said to ‘bind’ and ‘impel’ (instigare), and can of course be obeyed or disobeyed.[362] Our own Burton follows Aquinas in substance, but will not stretch the word conscience to cover synteresis. For him there are: (1) synteresis, which is knowledge of good and evil; (2) a dictamen rationis, a precept or injunction of reason which ‘admonishes’ to do the one and 195 forbear from the other; (3) the conscience which then justifies or condemns what we have done.[363] Jeremy Taylor makes the semantic situation unusually clear by noting the ancient meaning of conscientia—Horace’s conscire sibi—and saying that while this is correct so far as it goes it is not ‘full and adequate; for it only signifies conscience as it is a witness, not as a guide’. Under the name conscience we must also include ‘that which is called synteresis, or the general repository of moral principles’.[364]

If popular language had followed these distinctions, much confusion, and perhaps not a little bloodshed, would have been avoided. But that is not the way of common language. It would have nothing to do with the word synteresis though it was ready to talk abundantly about the thing. It therefore used the single word conscience, sometimes to mean the consciring of what we have done, sometimes the Inner Lawgiver who tells us what we should or should not do, sometimes the inner nagger or prompter that urges us to obey the Lawgiver here and now, and sometimes other things as well. All the senses work upon, and in and out through, one another, and often, no doubt, men did not know themselves, much less make clear to others, exactly what they meant. There are, it is true, passages where we find synderesis in more or less popular texts. Deguileville in his Pilgrimage of the Life of Man defines it as the higher part of reason whereby a man can learn how to govern his conscience.[365] This is intelligible 196 but would not much help a reader who had never met the word before. In the Assembly of Gods (ll. 932-8) we learn no more, and perhaps the poet knew no more, than that synderesis and conscience are somehow connected. Nothing was likely to come of either passage. The word had no future and does not occur in Johnson’s Dictionary. Todd’s supplemented edition of Johnson (1818) gives it with an erroneous definition and quotes only one example.

Conscience is thus left with a maze—or, better, a simmering pot—of meanings which we must now try to investigate.

VII. SURVIVAL OF THE SENSE ‘CONSCIRING’

This continues to flourish unimpaired to the present day. We can still have a ‘guilty conscience’, that is a consciring of guilt; for it is certainly not the inner lawgiver who is guilty. Thus we find a ‘coumbred conscience’;[366] ‘clearness of conscience’;[367] a ‘grieved conscience’.[368] The Prayer Book urges us to ‘examine our own consciences’ and suggests confession for any who cannot ‘quiet his own conscience’. Conscience is still the witness, though with added reference to the judge-before-whom, when Taylor says it ‘doth excuse or accuse a man before God’.[369] A slight and not unnatural confusion is perhaps creeping in when Cranmer talks of feeling ‘our conscience at peace with God’.[370] Why is it our conscience (whether as witness or lawgiver) rather than we who are at peace? Here, as throughout, we 197 must remember the intense emotional pressure of the experience the words refer to; in this circumambient emotion the separate semantic rights, so to speak, of the culprit soul and the witness get confused.

VIII. THE LAWGIVER

We have seen that already for Menander suneidesis was theos. When synteresis (whether distinguished in name from conscience or not) is being thought about within a Christian frame of reference, the tendency to regard it as a separate, and special, and specially divine, faculty in man, will be increased. For the inner lawgiver must now be conceived either as God himself or as his specially appointed lieutenant in the soul. Who else could claim such legislative rights? ‘Conscience (suneidesis) is God’, says Tatian. ‘It is the whiteness of eternal light, the spotless mirror of God’s majesty and the image of his goodness’, says St Bernard; ‘the corrector and paedagogus of the soul’, says Origen; God ‘rules in us by his substitute, our conscience’, says Taylor, from whom I take these quotations.[371] So in Milton, where God says ‘I will place within them as a guide My umpire conscience’.[372] ‘I feel not this deity in my bosom’, says the conscienceless Antonio, scoffing, but none the less showing how those who did not scoff regarded the matter.[373] Even hardier—for he spoke not ‘rapt above the Pole’ but standing on the floor of an Elizabethan House of Commons—are the words of Edward Aglionby: ‘the conscience of man is 198 eternal, invisible, and not in the power of the greatest monarchy in the world in any limits to be straitened, in any bounds to be constrained’.[374] Less exalted in language but, well weighed, no narrower in its claim, is Butler’s assertion that ‘Conscience does not only offer itself to show us the way we should walk in, but it likewise carries its own authority with it that it is our natural guide; the guide assigned to us by the Author of our nature’.[375]

Expressions of this sort are not, I think, to be found in the New Testament. They neither arise from it nor lead back to it. The claims made for conscience as something beyond ‘the power of the greatest monarchy in the world’ because it was God’s vicegerent will be repeated in later times by ‘conscientious objectors’ of all kinds; including those who claimed (in my opinion rightly) freedom to obey their conscience by maintaining that God does not exist.

One whimsical result of making conscience a name for synteresis is that the adjective ‘good’ when applied to it may now have a quite new sense. Immemorially—and still in the commonest usage—a ‘good conscience’, Seneca’s bona conscientia—means a good consciring, that is, a consciring of good or, more usually, a consciring of no evil. This is what it means in the Prayer Book when the compilers claim that it ‘doth not contain any thing which a godly man may not with a good conscience use’—anything which he would conscire to himself that he had sinned in using. But it means something totally 199 different when Hall (1649) says ‘A good conscience will tell you . . . you are bound to make restitution’;[376] if your synteresis or inner lawgiver is a good or sound one—if it is functioning properly—it will tell you this. The ambiguity is prettily seized by George MacDonald: ‘she was sorely troubled with what is, by huge discourtesy, called a bad conscience—being in reality a conscience doing its duty so well that it makes the whole house uncomfortable’.[377]

IX. DIVERSITY OF CONSCIENCES

I must here, for a moment, adopt what I know to be a false simplicity.

The more boldly men claim that conscience is, directly or vicariously, a divine lawgiver and the ‘spotless mirror of God’s majesty’, the more troublesomely aware they must become that this lawgiver gives different laws to different men; this mirror reflects different faces. Hence we have consciences in the plural, not meaning those different conscirings which different men must obviously have but those different inner laws they acknowledge. Thus Whitgift writes that such an alteration of the Church as the Puritans demand would cause ‘offence to many consciences’[378]—many men have a synteresis which will forbid them to accept it. Butler complains that the Presbyterians force all people to become ‘Saints’, though ‘against their consciences’.[379] The preface to the Prayer Book mentions ‘such alterations . . . as should be thought 200 requisite for the ease of tender consciences’, for some men have a synteresis so ‘tender’, so sensitive, that it forbids what others with a less exacting inner lawgiver would feel free to do. Hence, inconveniently, almost any man can claim exemption from the laws of the state on the ground that his own peculiar synteresis (is it not a far higher law?) forbids him to obey them, so that ‘nothing is more usual than to pretend conscience to all the actions of man which are public’.[380] Pretend does not mean ‘simulate’, but ‘put forward’ or ‘plead’. On Taylor’s view such men are right in obeying their synteresis even when their synteresis itself is wrong; for it is man’s lawful sovereign and in such cases ‘the king is misinformed, but the inferiors are bound to obey’.[381]

Hence arise the conceptions of ‘forcing’ or ‘freedom’ of consciences. Thus in Hudibras (I, i, 765) ‘Liberty of consciences’. Thus Robinson Crusoe, shortly before his departure from the island, finds himself absolute sovereign over a Protestant, a Pagan, and a Papist, but adds ‘I allowed liberty of conscience throughout my dominions’. Everyone will remember Milton’s ‘New Forcers of Conscience’ in the sonnet. Language does not always make quite clear whether the liberty in question is that of having a certain synteresis, or of endeavouring by persuasion to make the synteresis of other men more like your own, or of obeying your own synteresis in overt action, or all three.

But this, as I have warned the reader, is an over-simplification.

201

X. PRECARIOUSNESS OF THE SENSE ‘LAWGIVER’

The over-simplification lies in the attempt to isolate the inner lawgiver from the intellectual context in which he speaks. No lawgiver, inner or outer, gives laws in a vacuum; he always has real or supposed facts in mind, an idea of what is, which influences his rulings about what ought to be. Thus the outer lawgiver ceases to make new statutes against witchcraft when he ceases to believe in it, and does not make vaccination compulsory till he thinks it will prevent smallpox. It is the same with the inner lawgiver. If you believe in the Christian God, synteresis will lay upon you many duties towards him, and if you disbelieve, it will not. If you believe in transubstantiation it will tell you to risk Tyburn by attending Mass, and if you believe the Mass to be idolatry it will tell you to risk Smithfield by abstaining from it. It is indeed extremely difficult to find a pure difference of synteresis, one that does not flow from different beliefs about matter of fact. Perhaps the belief that it is in any possible circumstances wrong to kill a man, or that non-Aryans have no rights against the Herrenvolk, or that justice is the will of the people, might rank as ‘pure’. But for the most part the imperatives of the lawgiving synteresis are conditioned by the indicatives of each man’s belief or ‘convictions’. The two together make up what would now perhaps be called an ‘ideology’.

Philosophers and theologians, no doubt, will usually draw the distinction and will see that the high claims which can plausibly be made for the imperatives cannot 202 with equal plausibility be made for the indicatives. ‘Since you think A, do B’ might conceivably be a ‘divine’ voice. But the opinion that A is true—which may involve answers to all sorts of problems in ecclesiastical history, Greek and Hebrew scholarship, textual criticism, the nature of authority, international law, or the interpretation of Karl Marx—is clearly in a different position. Ordinary language, however, makes no distinctions. In it, your reasons for thinking the Mass holy or idolatrous and your consequent duty to go, or not to go, to it are both equally conscience. Side by side with this confusion, we have (I think) a faint influence from the Middle English usage mentioned above in section IIconscience as ‘mind’ or ‘thought’. As a result, we shall find the word sliding from the full sense of synteresis into that of profound conviction about truth and thence into that of mere opinion (about comparatively trivial matters), yet often carrying with it overtones from the idea of consciring. That is why I spoke about a simmering pot of meanings; any ingredient may be flavoured by any other.

XI. MIXED USAGES

We should all agree it was for conscience’ sake that Sir Thomas More refused to take the Oath of Supremacy. But in how many different senses? Urged by the Lord Chancellor to observe that all the bishops, universities, and scholars in England had agreed to the Act, More replied that he did not see ‘why that thing in my conscience should make any change’, for by going outside England and back into the past he could find a greater 203 weight of authority on his side; ‘therefore I am not bound, my lord, to conform my conscience to the council of one realm against the general council of Christendom’.[382] Here neither the Chancellor’s claim nor More’s answer has any bearing on the law given by synteresis that you must not swear what is false. The question at issue is whether the thing he is asked to swear to is false or not. If More had been an obscure private person, not called upon to swear but merely forming an opinion on Henry’s supremacy, the formation of that opinion would hardly have been a matter of conscience in the sense of synteresis. When he says that the decision of the English authorities will not alter his conscience, does he mean ‘will not alter my conception of my duty’ or ‘will not alter my view’ (on which, of course, the duty is based)? Probably both, but language does not of itself make this plain.

In this passage the indicative (Henry is not the head of the Church in England) and the imperative (Thou shalt not forswear thyself) are so closely linked both in logic and in emotion that the double meaning is almost inevitable. We come a little further when More, earlier in the same book, says it was not likely he would disclose to the government Tool (Mr Rich) ‘the secrets of my conscience touching the King’s Supremacy’. I think this means principally ‘my private opinion’, perhaps with some notion of consciring—‘the opinion to which I alone am privy’. Another passage from Roper carries us further still. The Chancellor asks Lord Fitzjames whether the indictment against More is ‘sufficient’ and gets the cautious 204 reply ‘If the act of parliament be not unlawful, then is the indictment in my conscience not insufficient’. Fitzjames is giving a judge’s reply; conscience must mean ‘opinion’.

But I would not say it means simply ‘opinion’. The word has not completely lost touch either with the sense ‘synteresis’ nor with the sense ‘consciring’. This will perhaps become clearer if we add two other examples. Pepys writes, ‘The Duke did, to my Lord’s dishonour, often say that he did in his conscience know the contrary to what he then said’ (in a dispute about a game of cards).[383] The disguised King in Henry V says ‘By my troth, I will speak my conscience of the King’ (IV, i, 119). In these, as in Fitzjames’s reply, conscience does indeed mean ‘what I think’ (or, in Pepys, ‘know’). But to get the exact shade of meaning I believe we should translate it ‘what I really think’, or ‘my honest opinion’, or (in Pepys) ‘he really knew very well’. That is how this usage is still flavoured by the other meanings of conscience. In all three examples we may infer some motive for evading or lying. If, despite this, you say what you really think or know, you are (a) uttering your conscience in the Middle English sense, declaring your actual mind; (b) obeying your conscience (synteresis) one of whose laws is ‘Tell the truth’; (c) revealing what you conscire to yourself as your secret opinion or knowledge. In the Pepysian passage there may lurk also the idea that my Lord will, after lying, have an unpleasant consciring (mala conscientia) of the fact.

The word may seem to have lost all trace of an ethical meaning when, as Taylor says, ‘some men suspect their 205 brother of a crime and are persuaded, as they say, in conscience that he did it’.[384] But even here there is probably some muddy-minded assertion that the suspicion is sincerely held and was honestly come by; combined, no doubt, with a monstrous, though only half-conscious, attempt to dignify it by all the lofty associations which the word conscience derives from the meaning ‘synteresis’.

XII. CONSCIENCE AS FEAR

Even in ancient times, as we have seen, a ‘bad conscience’, that is, the consciring evil deeds to oneself, was associated with fear; fear of possible detection and punishment by men, or of punishment by the gods whose detection was certain. The Christian doctrine of certain judgement and (highly probable) damnation naturally linked conscience and fear even more tightly together. From the consciring ‘I have sinned’ to the fear ‘I may be damned’ the transition became instantaneous and invariable, so that it was not felt to be a transition at all. When this process is complete, the word conscience itself may come to mean simply ‘fear of hell’.

The process has not gone so far in Milton when Adam says ‘O conscience, into what abyss of fears And horrors hast thou driven me!’[385] Conscience is still the driver into that abyss, not the abyss itself. A slightly further stage has been reached in Book IV (ll. 23 f.) where conscience ‘wakes’ in Satan, not the memory of guilt, but ‘despair’, the ‘memory’ of past bliss, present misery, and greater misery to be expected in the future. Conscience here is 206 ‘of’ punishment, not of sin. So in Taylor ‘conscience is present with a message from God and the men feel inward causes of fear’.[386] In Bunyan’s Holy War it is Mr Conscience who explains that Emanuel’s last messenger ‘was a messenger of death’. Similarly in Johnson, ‘he that feels himself alarmed by his conscience’,[387] the fact that conscience, strictly speaking, testifies and thus is the occasion rather than the source of the alarm, disappears.

But some usages go beyond this. Latimer says ‘when with the eye of his conscience . . . he beheld the horror of death and hell’.[388] Punishment has completely replaced sin as the object or content of conscience. Taylor, here again, is instructive. He says that, on ‘viewing’ the legislation of synteresis, conscience ‘binds to duty’, but on viewing ‘the act’ (our own past act) ‘it binds to punishment or consigns to comfort’.[389] Surely he unwittingly uses the verb bind in two quite different senses, of which the first (obliging) is clearly proper to the inner lawgiver but the second (condemning to) is not, or not in the same way; it is an executive act and, if a command at all, a command to the hangman not the culprit. And indeed bind in this sense is barely English. I suspect that Taylor is trying to find room for ‘fear of punishment’ as one of the senses of conscience without admitting to himself that it has, historically, very little claim to that position and may even be regarded as a semantic degradation. The furthest stage of all is reached by Henry More—the last author in whom I expected to find it—who embodies this sense in a 207 definition: ‘And first, of natural conscience, it is plain that it is a fear and confusion of mind arising from the presage of some mischief that may befall a man beside the ordinary course of Nature or the usuall occurrences of affairs because he hath done thus or thus.’ To be sure, it is only ‘natural’ conscience, pagan conscience, that he is defining. But he is ignoring the element of synteresis, the judgement of good and evil, even in it. His conscience would cover the merely prudential avoidance of ‘unlucky’ actions (Antidote, I, 10).

I feel almost certain that we here have the clue to Hamlet’s use of conscience at the end of the famous soliloquy (III, i, 83), where I believe it means nothing more or less than ‘fear of Hell’. I see that a case can be made for taking it to mean ‘reflection, thought’—an instance of the Middle English sense, belonging to the weakened branch. And this is even supported by the ‘pale cast of thought’ two lines later. But when we remember the passages already quoted from Richard III (‘conscience . . . makes a man a coward’, ‘O coward conscience’); and the close linking, which finally leads to the actual identification, of conscience with fear of punishment; and the fact that fears of ‘what dreams may come’ and ‘ills we know not of’ are the very reflections which have ‘sicklied o’er’ the native hue of Hamlet’s resolution; I think we must interpret the passage otherwise. In Latimer and Henry More we see the consciring of sin confused or equated with the fear of future suffering. Hamlet goes a step further. He says nothing at all about sins to be conscired; he fears future suffering, and he calls 208 that fear conscience. It must of course be remembered that sins to be conscired, in every man, would be taken for granted. When once fear of the next world had been mentioned they would be understood.

XIII. RAMIFICATIONS OF THE SENSE ‘SYNTERESIS’

‘I will make a Star Chamber matter of it’, says Shallow.[390] You may or may not bring Falstaff’s poaching before that tribunal; similarly, a man may or may not bring this or that of his actions before the inner tribunal of conscience; for most people think that at least some choices—say, having a boiled or a buttered egg—are ‘morally indifferent’ and do not fall under conscience’ jurisdiction. When we bring an act before the tribunal we make it a ‘matter’ (or ‘case’) of conscience just as Shallow would make poaching a Star Chamber ‘matter’. Thus Burton says of religious melancholics, ‘I see them make matters of conscience of such toys and trifles’.[391] ‘Some think it a great matter of conscience to depart from a piece of the least of their ceremonies’, says the Prayer Book (Of Ceremonies). In these cases it is scrupulosity that burdens the court of conscience with unnecessary business. But moral laxity, eager for loopholes and hence fruitful in fine distinctions, may do the same; ‘when men have no love to God, and desire but just to save their souls, and weigh grains and scruples, and give to God no more than they must needs, they shall multiply cases of conscience to a number which no books will contain’.[392]

209

Very often, where the thought to be expressed is exactly the same, the words ‘matter of’ or ‘case of’ are omitted, so that Burton can write ‘we make a conscience of every toy’;[393] or in Bunyan’s Mr Badman we read ‘a family where the governors . . . made conscience of the worship and service of God’ (thought it their duty to have family prayers). So Taylor: ‘He is a good man, and makes conscience of his ways’[394]—brings before the inner tribunal all that should be brought.

Some more difficult usages remain. ‘My conscience will serve me to run away from this Jew my master’, says Gobbo.[395] Conscience here means, I think, not the faculty but the content of synteresis, not the lawgiver but the law he gives. There is nothing (or nothing that can’t be got round) in Gobbo’s internal Statute Book which rules out running away. To be sure, the rest of his soliloquy shows this claim to be far from true, but we are concerned with its meaning. Something of the same process possibly accounts for Hamlet’s ‘Is’t not perfect conscience To quit with this arm?’ (V, ii, 67). As we say ‘it’s the law’, meaning ‘it is what the law permits (or enjoins)’, Hamlet describes, perhaps, as ‘perfect conscience’ what any sound synteresis would approve. Along the same line we may reach Iago’s generalisation about the ladies of Venice, that ‘their best conscience Is not to leave’t undone, but keep’t unknown’.[396] This might mean that the only (and therefore the best) precept contained in their synteresis is ‘Thou shalt not be found out’.

210

All such semantic bridges are, however, conjectural, and it is most improbable that the authors I quote could have enlightened us on the semantic history of their own expressions.

The words of the money-lender in Wilson’s Usury give rise to more than one problem. ‘It may bee’, he says, ‘there is some shifte to save a man’s conscience wyth all’.[397] If save means ‘salve’,[398] ‘heal’, or ‘soothe’, conscience will here be principally consciring; the usurer wants something which will silence the internal witness and make him feel comfortable. But he may speak of ‘saving’ his synteresis—as one ‘saves’ one’s credit or ‘face’—in the sense of enabling it without disgrace, without loss of all its high pretensions, to issue more lenient laws.

XIV. RETURN TO THE WEAKENED BRANCH

We have already observed that English conscious retained even to the nineteenth century the together sense and was therefore a synonym for Latin conscius. But a weakened sense was growing up at the same time. The noun consciousness had a similar history, for though it was formed later than conscience it was not formed in order to express a new meaning, but was at first a useless synonym.

211

The gradations between the original (together) sense of both words and that which both now bear are very fine. The extremes are clear. When they are used absolutely (‘the patient is conscious’, ‘the injection removed all consciousness’) the modern—and dangerous—sense is fully present. When either is followed by to the drift towards the dangerous sense (so far as concerns that author and that context) has not yet begun; thus the N.E.D. quotes from a seventeenth-century author ‘their consciousness to themselves of their ignorance’, and, more strikingly, from Berkeley ‘God is conscious to our innermost thoughts’ (Principles). Here the idea of consciring is obviously at work. In between these two extremes come the doubtful cases.

Of large and irregular assemblies Hobbes says ‘he that cannot render a particular and good account of his being amongst them is to be judged conscious of an unlawfull and tumultuous designe’.[399] This is almost certainly the together sense; if conscious of meant merely ‘aware of’ it would imply no complicity; a government spy might be so aware. When Locke says ‘To be happy or miserable without being conscious of it seems . . . impossible’[400] the dangerous sense (‘aware’) is almost full-blown. Almost, but perhaps not quite. Locke may be saying something more than that an un-felt misery is not a misery. What that something more could be is apparent from Clarke’s definition, ‘Consciousness in the most strict and exact sense of the word signifies . . . the Reflex act by which I know that I know and that my thoughts . . . are my own 212 and not another’s’.[401] Consciousness is here something very like the medieval common sense, something distinguishable from mere sentience,[402] and something whose absence would be not quite identical with what most speakers today call ‘unconsciousness’. There would still be a slight together sense—myself consciring my thoughts as mine. But notice that Clarke has to qualify this as ‘the most strict and exact sense’; a looser, and more weakened, sense was presumably current. I think Locke is using it, if not in the passage I have quoted yet in the very next paragraph, when he says the soul ‘must necessarily be conscious of its own perceptions’.

I am very puzzled as to what Pope meant when he wrote

The forests wondered at th’unusual grain

And secret transport touch’d the conscious swain.[403]

If conscious here bears the dangerous sense, one wonders why we need be told that the swain who felt transport was neither fainting, asleep nor anaesthetised. If it means ‘consciring’, what was this mystery to which he was privy? Why, if it comes to that, was his transport so ‘secret’? What ‘touched’ him was the sight of ‘yellow harvests’, approved by ‘monarchs’. Or is it, as the following lines perhaps suggest, that the swain was in a secret because, in all this, he saw—and monarchs did not—‘fair Liberty’ beginning to rear ‘her cheerful head’? We are on firmer ground when Cowper speaks of having 213 ‘borne the ruffling wind, scarce conscious that it blew’.[404] This is the weakened sense, though not yet in its absolute use.

While these senses obviously belong to the weakened branch, there is no evidence so far as I know that they descend from that language in which the weakened branch flourished without rival; in other words that they were influenced by French. They are an independent effort of our own language to provide itself with necessary tools of thought.

214

9
AT THE FRINGE OF LANGUAGE

Language exists to communicate whatever it can communicate. Some things it communicates so badly that we never attempt to communicate them by words if any other medium is available. Those who think they are testing a boy’s ‘elementary’ command of English by asking him to describe in words how one ties one’s tie or what a pair of scissors is like, are far astray. For precisely what language can hardly do at all, and never does well, is to inform us about complex physical shapes and movements. Hence descriptions of such things in the ancient writers are nearly always unintelligible. Hence we never in real life voluntarily use language for this purpose; we draw a diagram or go through pantomimic gestures. The exercises which such examiners set are no more a test of ‘elementary’ linguistic competence than the most difficult bit of trick-riding from the circus ring is a test of elementary horsemanship.

Another grave limitation of language is that it cannot, like music or gesture, do more than one thing at once. However the words in a great poet’s phrase interinanimate one other and strike the mind as a quasi-instantaneous chord, yet, strictly speaking, each word must be read or heard before the next. That way, language is as unilinear 215 as time. Hence, in narrative, the great difficulty of presenting a very complicated change which happens suddenly. If we do justice to the complexity, the time the reader must take over the passage will destroy the feeling of suddenness. If we get in the suddenness we shall not be able to get in the complexity. I am not saying that genius will not find its own ways of palliating this defect in the instrument; only that the instrument is in this way defective.

One of the most important and effective uses of language is the emotional. It is also, of course, wholly legitimate. We do not talk only in order to reason or to inform. We have to make love and quarrel, to propitiate and pardon, to rebuke, console, intercede, and arouse. ‘He that complains’, said Johnson, ‘acts like a man, like a social being.’ The real objection lies not against the language of emotion as such, but against language which, being in reality emotional, masquerades—whether by plain hypocrisy or subtler self-deceit—as being something else.

All my generation are much indebted to Dr I. A. Richards for having fully called our attention to the emotional functions of language. But I am hardly less indebted to Professor Empson for having pointed out that the conception of emotional language can be very easily extended too far.[405] It was time to call a halt.

We must obviously not call any utterance ‘emotional’ language because it in fact arouses, even because it must arouse, emotion. ‘It is not cancer after all’, ‘The Germans have surrendered’, ‘I love you’—may all be true statements 216 about matter of fact. And of course it is the facts, not the language, that arouse the emotion. In the last the fact communicated is itself the existence of an emotion but that makes no difference. Statements about crime are not criminal language; nor are statements about emotions necessarily emotional language. Nor, in my opinion, are value-judgements (‘this is good’, ‘this is bad’) emotional language. Approval and disapproval do not seem to me to be emotions. If we felt at all times about the things we judge good the emotion which is appropriate, our lives would be easier. It would also be an error to treat ‘I am washed in the blood of the Lamb’ as emotional language. It is of course metaphorical language. But by his metaphor the speaker is trying to communicate what he believes to be a fact. You may of course think the belief false in his particular case. You may think the real universe is such that no fact which corresponded to such a statement could possibly occur. You may say that the real cause which prompts a man to say things like that is a state of emotion. But if so, an emotion has produced erroneous belief about an impossible fact, and it is the fact erroneously believed in which the man is stating. A man’s hasty belief that the Germans had surrendered (before they did) might well be caused by his emotions. That would not make ‘The Germans have surrendered’ a specimen of emotional language. If you could find a man nowadays capable of believing, and saying, ‘The Russians have all been annihilated by magic’, even this would not be emotional language, though his belief in magic might be a belief engendered by emotion.

217

All this is fairly plain sailing. We reach something harder in the things said by poets. For there the purpose of the utterance would be frustrated if no emotion were aroused. They do not merely, like the sentences cited above, arouse emotion in fact; it is their purpose—at any rate, part of their purpose—to do so. But we must be very careful here. Having observed that a poetical utterance in fact arouses emotion, and is intended to arouse emotion, and that if taken as a statement about reality—or even about the make-believe ‘realities’ of a fictitious narrative—it would be nonsensical or at least false, can we conclude that it communicates nothing but emotion? I think not.

Nothing will convince me that ‘My soul is an enchanted boat’[406] is simply a better way—however much better—of doing what might be done by some exclamation like ‘Gee!’ Asia has risen from the dark cave of Demogorgon. She is floating upwards. She is saluted as ‘Life of Life!’ The reversed temporal process in ll. 97-103 (‘We have passed Age’s icy caves’ etc.), borrowed from Plato’s Politicus (269c sq.), marks the fact that at this moment the whole cycle is reversed and cosmos begins anew. She is undergoing apotheosis. What did it feel like? The poet says to us in effect ‘Think of going in a boat. But quite effortless’ (‘Like a sleeping swan’ gliding with the current, he adds in the next line), ‘Like a boat without sail or oar; the motive power undiscoverable. Like a magic boat—you must have read or dreamed of such things—a boat drawn on, drawn swiftly on, irresistibly, smoothly, by enchantment.’ Exactly. I know now how it felt for Asia. 218 The phrase has communicated emotion. But notice how. By addressing in the first instance my imagination. He makes me imagine a boat rushing over waves, which are also identified with sounds. After that he need do no more; my emotion will follow of itself. Poetry most often communicates emotions, not directly, but by creating imaginatively the grounds for those emotions. It therefore communicates something more than emotion; only by means of that something more does it communicate the emotion at all.

Burns compares his mistress to ‘a red, red rose’; Wordsworth his to ‘a violet by a mossy stone Half hidden from the eye’. These expressions do communicate to me the emotion each poet felt. But it seems to me that they do so solely by forcing me to imagine two (very different) women. I see the rose-like, overpowering, midsummer sweetness of the one; the reticent, elusive freshness, the beauty easily overlooked in the other. After that my emotions may be left to themselves. The poets have done their part.

This, which is eminently true of poetry, is true of all imaginative writing. One of the first things we have to say to a beginner who has brought us his MS. is, ‘Avoid all epithets which are merely emotional. It is no use telling us that something was “mysterious” or “loathsome” or “awe-inspiring” or “voluptuous”. Do you think your readers will believe you just because you say so? You must go quite a different way to work. By direct description, by metaphor and simile, by secretly evoking powerful associations, by offering the right stimuli to our 219 nerves (in the right degree and the right order), and by the very beat and vowel-melody and length and brevity of your sentences, you must bring it about that we, we readers, not you, exclaim “how mysterious!” or “loathsome” or whatever it is. Let me taste for myself, and you’ll have no need to tell me how I should react to the flavour.’

In Donne’s couplet

Your gown going off, such beautious state reveals

As when from flowry meads th’hills shadow steales[407]

beautious is the only word of the whole seventeen which is doing no work.

There are exceptions to this principle. By very successful placing, a great author may sometimes raise such words to poetic life. Wordsworth’s lines are a specimen:

Which, to the boundaries of space and time,

Of melancholy space and doleful time,

Superior—[408]

Here we have almost the reverse of the process I have been describing. The object (space and time) is in one way so familiar to our imaginations and in another so unimaginable—we have read so many tedious attempts to exalt or over-awe us with mere superlatives or even with simple arithmetic—that nothing can be made of it. This time, therefore, the poet withdraws the object (the ground for emotion) altogether and appeals directly to our emotions; and not to the quite obvious ones. Another exception is naturally to be found in drama or very dramatic lyric, 220 where the poet—with discretion and a proper use of illusion—imitates the speech of people in some highly emotional situation—even, at need, their inarticulate cries. This in its purity, which purity a good poet never sustains for long, belongs to poetry not in so far as poetry is a special use of language but in so far as poetry is mimesis. In themselves the ‘Ah! Ah!’ or ‘Otototoi’ or ‘Iou! Iou!’ of characters in a Greek tragedy are not specimens of poetry any more than the ‘Bé, bé’ of the lamb or the ‘Au! Au!’ of the dog in Aristophanes.

In general, however, the poet’s route to our emotions lies through our imaginations.

We must also exclude from the category ‘emotional language’ words such as I have taken supernatural to be. The class of things which they refer to may be bound together chiefly by a common emotion; but the purpose of using the words is to assign something to that class, not merely to communicate the emotion which led to the classification.

Having thus narrowed the field, we can now make a new start. It will be noticed that I have throughout used the word emotional rather than emotive. This is because I think the latter word applicable to only one aspect of emotional language. For an ‘emotive word’ ought to mean one whose function is to arouse emotion. But surely we ought to distinguish utterances which arouse, from those which express, emotion? The first is directed towards producing some effect on a (real or imagined) hearer; the second discharges our own emotion, cleanses our stuffed bosom of some perilous stuff.

221

The distinction will seem straw-splitting if we have in mind the language of love. For, as Samson says, ‘love seeks to have love’, and it would be hard to say whether endearments serve more as expressions of love in the speaker or incitements to it in the beloved. But that tells us more about the nature of love than about the nature of language. One of my old headmasters once wisely said it was a pity that amare was the first Latin verb we all learn. He thought this led to an imperfect grasp of the difference between the active and the passive voice. It might be better to begin with flagellare. The difference between flogging and being flogged would come home to the business and bosoms of schoolboys far more effectively than that of loving and being loved. On the same principle, we can best see the distinction between the stimulant and the expressive functions of emotional language in a quarrel; and best of all where the same word performs both. The man who calls me a low hound both expresses and (actually or intentionally) stimulates emotion. But not the same emotion. He expresses contempt; he stimulates, or hopes to stimulate, the almost opposite emotion of humiliation.

Again, in the language of complaint we often find the expressive without the stimulant. When two people who have missed the last train stand on the silent platform saying ‘Damn’ or ‘Bloody’ or ‘Sickening’, they neither intend nor need to stimulate each other’s disappointment. They are just ‘getting it off their chests’.

The vocabulary of endearment, complaint, and abuse, provides, I think, almost the only specimens of words that are purely emotional, words from which all imaginative 222 or conceptual content has vanished, so that they have no function at all but to express or stimulate emotion, or both. And an examination of them soon convinces us that in them we see language at its least linguistic. We have come to the frontier between language and inarticulate vocal sounds. And at that frontier we find a two-way traffic going on.

On the one hand we find inarticulate sounds becoming words with a fixed spelling and a niche in the dictionary. Thus English heigh-ho and Latin eheu are clearly formalised imitations of the sigh; ah, of the gasp; tut-tut, of the tongue clicked against the hard palate. These are general. In particular situations the ‘verbification’ of the inarticulate may occur ad hoc. A voluntary scream may become a cry for mercy. A voluntary groan, from a wounded man, uttered to attract the attention of the stretcher-bearers, may be the equivalent of a sentence (‘There is a wounded man in this ditch’).

But we also see the frontier being crossed in the opposite direction. In the vocabulary of abuse and complaint we see things that once were words passing out of the realm of language (properly so called) and becoming the equivalents of inarticulate sounds or even of actions; of sighs, moans, whimperings, growls, or blows.

The ‘swear-words’—damn for complaint and damn you for abuse—are a good example. Historically the whole Christian eschatology lies behind them. If no one had ever consigned his enemy to the eternal fires and believed that there were eternal fires to receive him, these ejaculations would never have existed. But inflation, the spontaneous 223 hyperboles of ill temper, and the decay of religion, have long since emptied them of that lurid content. Those who have no belief in damnation—and some who have—now damn inanimate objects which would on any view be ineligible for it. The word is no longer an imprecation. It is hardly, in the full sense, a word at all when so used. Its popularity probably owes as much to its resounding phonetic virtues as to any, even fanciful, association with hell. It has ceased to be profane. It has also become very much less forceful. You may say the same of sickening in its popular, ejaculatory, use. There are alarms and disappointments which can actually produce nausea, or, at least, emotions which we feel to be somehow similar to it. But the man who says sickening! when he has missed the train is not thinking about that. The word is simply an alternative to damn or bloody. And of course far weaker than it would be if it still carried any suggestion of vomiting.

So with abusive terms. No one would now call his schoolfellow or next door neighbour a swine unless someone had once used this word to make a real comparison between his enemy and a pig. It is now a mere alternative to beast or brute or various popular unprintable words. They are all interchangeable. Villain, as we know, once really compared your enemy to a villein. Once, to call a man cad or knave assigned to him the status of a servant. And it did so because, earlier still, these words meant ‘boy’ or ‘junior’ (you address a slave as ‘boy’ in Greek and a waiter as garçon in French).

Thus all these words have come down in the world. 224 None of them started by being merely abusive, few of them by being abusive at all. They once stimulated emotion by suggesting an image. They made the enemy odious or contemptible by asserting he was like somebody or something we already disliked or looked down on. Their use was a sort of passionate parody of the syllogism: pigs (or servants or my juniors) are contemptible—John is like a pig (or servant or adolescent)—therefore John is contemptible. That was why they really hurt; because hurting was not the whole of what they did. They stimulated emotion because they also stimulated something else; imagination. They stimulated emotion in the particular case because they exploited emotions which already existed towards whole classes of things or persons. Now that they are nothing whatever but emotional stimulants, they are weak emotional stimulants. They make no particular accusation. They tell us nothing except that the speaker has lost his temper.

And even this they do not tell us linguistically, but symptomatically; as a red face, a loud voice, or a clenched fist, might do equally well. The fact of the other person’s anger may hurt or frighten us; hurt us if we love him, or frighten us if he is larger and younger than ourselves and threatens violence. But his language as such has very little power to do the only thing it is intended to do. It would have been far more wounding to be called swine when the word still carried some whiff of the sty and some echo of a grunt; far more wounding to be called a villain when this still conjured up an image of the unwashed, malodorous, ineducable, gross, belching, close-fisted, 225 and surly boor. Now, who cares? Language meant solely to hurt hurts strangely little.

This can be seen clearly when we catch a word ‘just on the turn’. Bitch is one. Till recently—and still in the proper contexts—this accused a woman of one particular fault and appealed, with some success, to our contempt by calling up an image of the she-dog’s comical and indecorous behaviour when she is on heat. But it is now increasingly used of any woman whom the speaker, for whatever reason, is annoyed with—the female driver who is in front of him, or a female magistrate whom he thinks unjust. Clearly, the word is far more wounding in its narrower usage. If that usage is ever totally lost—as I think it will be—the word will sink to the level of damn her. Notice, too, how cat (of a woman) is still strong and useful because the image is still alive in it.

An important principle thus emerges. In general, emotional words, to be effective, must not be solely emotional. What expresses or stimulates emotion directly, without the intervention of an image or concept, expresses or stimulates it feebly. And in particular, when words of abuse have hurting the enemy as their direct and only object, they do not hurt him much. In the field of language, however it may be in that of action, hatred cuts its own throat, and those who are too ‘willing to wound’ become thereby impotent to strike. And all this is only another way of saying that as words become exclusively emotional they cease to be words and therefore of course cease to perform any strictly linguistic function. They operate as growls or barks or tears. 226 ‘Exclusively’ is an important adverb here. They die as words not because there is too much emotion in them but because there is too little—and finally nothing at all—of anything else.

In this there is not much to be lamented. If a mother with a baby, or lovers in each other’s arms, use language so emotional that it is really not language at all, I see no ground for shame or offence; and if men in an orgy of resentment, though (in the physical sense) they articulate, are really no more speaking—are saying no more—than a snarling animal, this is perhaps all for the best. The real corruption comes when men whose purpose in speaking is in fact purely emotional conceal this from others, and perhaps from themselves, by words that seem to be, but are not, charged with a conceptual content.

We have all heard bolshevist, fascist, Jew, and capitalist, used not to describe but merely to insult. Rose Macaulay noticed a tendency to prefix ‘so called’ to almost any adjective when it was used of those the speaker hated; the final absurdity being reached when people referred to the Germans as ‘these so-called Germans’. Bourgeois and middle class often suffer the same fate.

A literary man of my acquaintance, on reading an unfavourable reference to his own works, called it vulgar. The charge brought against him was one that only highly educated people ever bring; the tone of the passage not otherwise offensive than by being unfavourable; the phrasing perfectly good English. If he had called it false, unintelligent, or malicious, I could have understood, though I might have disagreed. But why vulgar? Clearly, 227 this word was selected solely because the speaker thought it was the one that the enemy, if he could hear it, would most dislike. It was the equivalent of an oath or a growl. But that was concealed from the speaker because ‘This is vulgar’ sounds like a judgement.

When we write criticism we have to be continually on our guard against this sort of thing. If we honestly believe a work to be very bad we cannot help hating it. The function of criticism, however, is ‘to get ourselves out of the way and let humanity decide’; not to discharge our hatred but to expose the grounds for it; not to vilify faults but to diagnose and exhibit them. Unfortunately to express our hatred and to revenge ourselves is easier and more agreeable. Hence there is a tendency to select our pejorative epithets with a view not to their accuracy but to their power of hurting. If writing which was intended to be comic has set our teeth on edge, how easily the adjectives arch or facetious trickle out of the pen! But if we do not know exactly what we mean by them, if we are not prepared to say how comic work which errs by archness and facetiousness differs from comic work which errs in any other way, it is to be feared that we are really using them not to inform the reader but to annoy the author—arch or facetious being among the most effective ‘smear-words’ of our period. In the same way work which obviously aspires and claims to be mature, if the critic dislikes it, will be called adolescent; not because the critic has really seen that its faults are those of adolescence but because he has seen that adolescence is the last thing the author wishes or expects to be accused of.

228

The best protection against this is to remind ourselves again and again what the proper function of pejorative words is. The ultimate, simplest and most abstract, is bad itself. The only good purpose for ever departing from that monosyllable when we condemn anything is to be more specific, to answer the question ‘Bad in what way?’ Pejorative words are rightly used only when they do this. Swine, as a term of abuse is now a bad pejorative word, because it brings no one accusation rather than another against the person it vilifies; coward and liar are good ones because they charge a man with a particular fault—of which he might be proved guilty or innocent. As applied to literature, dull, hackneyed, incoherent, monotonous, pornographic, cacophonous, are good pejoratives; they tell people in what particular way we think a book faulty. Adolescent or provincial are not so good. For even when they are honestly used, to define, not merely to hurt, they really suggest a cause for the book’s badness instead of describing the badness itself. We are saying in effect ‘He was led into his faults by being immature’ or ‘by living in Lancashire’. But would it not be more interesting to indicate the faults themselves and leave out our historical theory about their causes? If we find words like these—and vulgar, and others—indispensable to our criticism, if we find ourselves applying them to more and more different kinds of things, there is grave reason to suspect that—whether we know it or not—we are really using them not to diagnose but to hurt. If so, we are assisting in verbicide. For this is the downward path which leads to the graveyard of murdered words. First they are 229 purely descriptive; adolescent tells us a man’s age, villain, his status. Then they are specifically pejorative; adolescent tells us that a man’s work displays ‘mawkishness and all the thousand bitters’ confessed by Keats, and villain tells that a man has a churl’s mind and manners. Then they become mere pejoratives, useless synonyms for bad, as villain did and as adolescent may do if we aren’t careful. Finally they become terms of abuse and cease to be language in the full sense at all.

As this book is now almost done, what would otherwise be a digression—for it carries us beyond the subject of vocabulary—may perhaps be excused as a sort of coda. In the last few paragraphs we have had to touch on criticism. I would be very glad if I could transfer to even one reader my conviction that adverse criticism, far from being the easiest, is one of the hardest things in the world to do well. And that for two reasons.

Dr I. A. Richards first seriously raised the problem of badness in literature. And his singularly honest wrestling with it shows how dark a problem it is. For when we try to define the badness of a work, we usually end by calling it bad on the strength of characteristics which we can find also in good work. Dr Richards began by hoping he had found the secret of badness in an appeal to stock responses. But Gray’s Elegy beat him. Here was a good poem which made that appeal throughout. Worse still, its particular goodness depended on doing so. This happens again and again. The novel before you is bad—a transparent compensatory fantasy projected by a poor, plain woman, erotically starving. Yes, but so is Jane Eyre. Another bad 230 book is amorphous; but so is Tristram Shandy. An author betrays shocking indifference to all the great political, social, and intellectual upheavals of his age; like Jane Austen. The solution of the problem is, I suspect, still far away.

The other difficulty lies within. As I said before, what we think thoroughly bad, we hate. If, besides being bad, it enjoys great popularity and thereby helps to exclude works that we approve from their ‘place in the sun’, hatred of a somewhat less disinterested sort will creep in. Lower and still lower levels of hatred may open; we may dislike the author personally, he and we may belong to opposed literary ‘parties’ or factions. The book before us becomes a symbol of l’infâme. Hence a perpetual danger of what is called criticism (judgement) becoming mere action—a blow delivered in a battle. But if it does, we are lost as critics.

Everyone who remembers Arnold’s ‘Literary Influence of Academies’ will see why we are lost. But its lesson has been forgotten. There has been in our time a determined, and successful, attempt to revive the brutalité des journaux anglais. Reviews so filled with venom have often been condemned socially for their bad manners, or ethically for their spite. I am not prepared to defend them from either charge; but I prefer to stress their inutility.

They can, no doubt, be enjoyed if we already agree with the critic. But then, you know, we are not reading them to inform our judgement. What we enjoy is a resounding blow by our own ‘side’. How useless they are for any strictly critical function becomes apparent if 231 we approach them with an open mind. I had this forced upon me when I read some unusually violent reviews lately which were all by the same man. My mind could not but be open. The books he reviewed were not by me nor by any close friend of mine. I had never heard of the critic. I read (at first—one soon learned to skip his productions) to find out what the books were like and whether I should consider buying them. But I found I could learn nothing about the books. In the first hundred words the critic had revealed his passions. What happened to me after that is, I think, what must happen to anyone in such circumstances. Automatically, without thinking about it, willy-nilly, one’s mind discounts everything he says; as it does when we are listening to a drunk or delirious man. Indeed we cannot even think about the book under discussion. The critic rivets our attention on himself. The spectacle of a man thus writhing in the mixed smart and titillation of a fully indulged resentment is, in its way, too big a thing to leave us free for any literary considerations. We are in the presence of tragi-comedy from real life. When we get to the end we find that the critic has told us everything about himself and nothing about the book.

Thus in criticism, as in vocabulary, hatred over-reaches itself. Willingness to wound, too intense and naked, becomes impotent to do the desired mischief.

Of course, if we are to be critics, we must condemn as well as praise; we must sometimes condemn totally and severely. But we must obviously be very careful; in their condemnations great critics long before our time have 232 exposed themselves. Is there any way in which we—lesser men than they—can avoid doing the same? I think perhaps there is. I think we must get it firmly fixed in our minds that the very occasions on which we should most like to write a slashing review are precisely those on which we had much better hold our tongues. The very desire is a danger signal. When an author whom we admire in general, writing in a genre we thoroughly enjoy, produces a disappointing work, we may proceed with tolerable safety. We know what we had hoped for. We see, and would have relished, what he was trying to do. By that light we may possibly diagnose where the book has gone wrong. But when an author we never could stand is attempting (unsuccessfully—or, worse still, successfully) ‘exactly the sort of thing we always loathe’, then, if we are wise, we shall be silent. The strength of our dislike is itself a probable symptom that all is not well within; that some raw place in our psychology has been touched, or else that some personal or partisan motive is secretly at work. If we were simply exercising judgement we should be calmer; less anxious to speak. And if we do speak, we shall almost certainly make fools of ourselves.

Continence in this matter is no doubt painful. But, after all, you can always write your slashing review now and drop it into the wastepaper basket a day or so later. A few re-readings in cold blood will often make this quite easy.

FOOTNOTES

[1]II, i, 261.
[2]The Structure of Complex Words (1951), p. 257.
[3]Preface to Book II.
[4]De Bello Gallico I, 21.
[5]Ars Poetica, 353.
[6]De Finibus IV, 7.
[7]Gen. i. 21.
[8]C. XIV, 144.
[9]C. XIX, 223.
[10]Pericles V, i, 68.
[11]Alfred’s Boethius, ed. W. J. Sedgefield (1899), p. 151.
[12]Vinaver, p. 245, l. 17. Not in Caxton.
[13]Vinaver, p. 714, l. 5. Not in Caxton.
[14]Arcadia II, xxvi, 4.
[15]Hen. VI, Pt 3, I, i, 82.
[16]XI, viii. Vinaver, pp. 804-5.
[17]Euphues and his England, ed. Arber (1919), p. 465.
[18]Chaucer, Troilus and Crysyde, IV, 768.
[19]XIX, x. Vinaver, p. 1147, l. 3, was for is.
[20]Arcadia II, 10, Rubric.
[21]Dialogue Against the Fever Pestilence (1564).
[22]Measure for Measure III, i, 225.
[23]C. VIII, 43.
[24]Antony and Cleopatra II, v, 78.
[25]XIV, vi. Vinaver, p. 912, l. 25.
[26]A. XI, 243.
[27]Canterbury Tales, A. 647.
[28]Persian Eclogues IV, 1.
[29]Dramatic Poesy. Essays, ed. Ker, vol. I, p. 54.
[30]Euripides, Bacchae, 651.
[31]Euripides, Helena, 87.
[32]Oed. Col. 1222.
[33]Fragment 8.
[34]Euripides, Medea, 103.
[35]Herodotus II, 5.
[36]Plato, Republic, 410 e.
[37]Politics, 1252 b.
[38]Cf. Metaphysics, 1014 b.
[39]Enneads V, viii, 1; some editions xxviii, 1.
[40]De Caelo III, 278 b.
[41]Metaphysics, 1064 a. Everyman trans. p. 156.
[42]Ibid. 1072 b. Trans. p. 346.
[43]Gerusalemme IX, 56.
[44]See Deguileville, Pilgrimage, trans. Lydgate, 3415.
[45]Phisicien’s Tale, C. 22.
[46]De Mundo, 392 a.
[47]Metaphysics, 1072 b.
[48]Paradise Lost II, 911.
[49]The gods of mythology, who had parents and a history and known birthplaces, were of course items in nature (d.s.).
[50]De Natura Deorum I, 14.
[51]Ibid. II, 57.
[52]Langland, C. XXIII, 80.
[53]Bernardus Silvester, Alanus ab Insulis.
[54]Romance of the Rose.
[55]Chaucer, Parlement, 379.
[56]Man of Law’s Tale, B. 298.
[57]Politics, 1254 a.
[58]Republic, 381 a.
[59]Euripides, Electra, 261.
[60]Spectator, 119.
[61]Paradise Lost IV, 241.
[62]Epistles XC, 44.
[63]Consolation II, Pr. v.
[64]Faerie Queene, II, vii, 15.
[65]P.L. V, 451.
[66]Romeo and Juliet II, iv, 92.
[67]Knight’s Tale, A. 2759.
[68]Conquest of Granada, Pt I, II, i.
[69]This degree of psycho-analysis is as old as Plato’s Republic, 571 a-572 d.
[70]Boswell, 12 April 1778.
[71]Line 227.
[72]Dejection, VI.
[73]Pilgrim’s Progress, Pt 2.
[74]Hen. IV, Pt 2, IV, v, 65.
[75]Essay on Criticism, 236.
[76]Life of Milton.
[77]Politics, 1252 b.
[78]Ibid. 1254 a.
[79]Johnson’s Preface to Shakespeare.
[80]Clearer for an understanding of the theory as usually held. Johnson has his own modification of it. Where others wanted the generality King or Senator to show through the individual Claudius or Menenius, he wanted the universal Man to show through the generality King or Senator.
[81]Tragedies of the Last Age. Spingarn, Critical Essays of the XVIIth Century, vol. II, p. 193.
[82]Ibid. p. 194.
[83]Poetics, 1451 a-b.
[84]Short View of Tragedy, ibid. p. 224.
[85]Ibid. p. 197.
[86]Poetics, 1454 a.
[87]Antigone, 453.
[88]Laws, I, xii.
[89]Epistle XC, 4, 38.
[90]Essay on Man III, 147.
[91]Leviathan, 13.
[92]Boswell, Hebrides, 22 August 1773.
[93]Hebrides, 27 October 1773.
[94]Life. Just before 29 April 1776.
[95]Castle of Health.
[96]Etymologies VIII, vi, 3.
[97]Julius Caesar II, i, 261.
[98]Tamburlaine, Pt 2, 3944.
[99]De Coelo III, 298 b.
[100]Saints’ Everlasting Rest III, xi.
[101]Universal Prayer.
[102]Essay on Man I, 267.
[103]Seasons I, 83.
[104]Task I, 749, Rerum Rusticarum III, i. ‘Divina natura gave the land (agros), but human art built cities’. Does divina natura mean ‘the divine nature’ (to theion, God) or the divine species (the gods) or nature (d.s.) (the goddess)? Or could Varro have told us?
[105]Aeneid I, 199.
[106]Calendar, Nov., 60, 70 etc.
[107]Aen. I, 151.
[108]P.L. XI, 585.
[109]Tristram Shandy IX, 33.
[110]Chronicle, ann. 937, l. 20.
[111]Fragment C. 6907.
[112]On Exodus xxxviii. 7.
[113]Aen. XI, 553.
[114]VI, iv. Vinaver, p. 259, l. 27.
[115]Manciple’s Tale, H. 275.
[116]R. Hope Robbins, Secular Lyrics of the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Centuries, no. 78, 63.
[117]E. 218.
[118]Knight’s Tale, A. 2602.
[119]I, Met. iv.
[120]F.Q. II, vii, 23.
[121]Much Ado I, i, 183.
[122]Boswell, 12 April 1778.
[123]Mansfield Park, ch. XXXVI.
[124]Boswell, 23 September 1777.
[125]Genesis B, 250.
[126]Beowulf, 2703.
[127]Hamlet III, ii, 336.
[128]Poema Morale 2; before 1200.
[129]Nosce Teipsum. Of the Soule, etc., stanza 15.
[130]Essay on Criticism I, 53.
[131]Absalom I, 161.
[132]See pp. 147 sq.
[133]Much Ado I, i, 63.
[134]Troilus II, 271.
[135]Histories II, 4.
[136]Epistle 95.
[137]Histories IV, 5.
[138]De Finibus V, 13.
[139]Annals I, i.
[140]Vesp. xviii.
[141]II, Pr. iii.
[142]Democritus to the Reader.
[143]Epist. II, i, 88.
[144]Defence of the Epilogue. Essays, ed. Ker, vol. I, p. 163.
[145]Quintilian VIII, iii.
[146]Ibid. II, iv.
[147]Essay on Criticism I, 82.
[148]Cicero, Ad Quintum II, ii. Some emend to ‘but not much art’. The choice of reading makes no difference for our purpose.
[149]E.C. II, 532.
[150]Quintilian, X, i.
[151]E.C. I, 17.
[152]De Arte, 295.
[153]L’Art Poétique IV, 78.
[154]I, 36.
[155]How far we have travelled from the neo-classic age and also how far it had travelled from the sixteenth century; for S.O.D. gives the date 1530 for its loftier sense.
[156]Ker, vol. I, p. 82.
[157]Ibid. vol. II, p. 102.
[158]Much Ado I, i, 57.
[159]Hen. IV, Pt 2, I, ii, 8.
[160]Preface to Gondibert.
[161]Discourse of the English Stage.
[162]Preface to Annus Mirabilis, Ker, vol. I, p. 14.
[163]Preface to The Sullen Lovers.
[164]Defence of the Epilogue, Ker, vol. I, p. 173.
[165]Preface to the Fables, Ker, vol. II, p. 256.
[166]Dramatic Poesy, Ker, vol. I, p. 72.
[167]Ibid. p. 92.
[168]Preface to Ovid’s Epistles, Ker, vol. I, pp. 233-4.
[169]Ode to Wit, stanza 8.
[170]Preface to Annus Mirabilis, Ker, vol. I, p. 14.
[171]The Author’s Apology etc., Ker, vol. I, p. 190.
[172]Ker, vol. I, p. 270.
[173]Spectator, 62.
[174]Essay on Criticism, II, 297.
[175]Italics mine. Defence of the Epilogue. Ker, vol. I, p. 172.
[176]E.C. II, 396.
[177]Spectator, 62.
[178]Life of Cowley.
[179]Cyropaedia III, ii, 23.
[180]St Augustine, Confessions IX, 8.
[181]Aristotle, Ethics, 1119 b.
[182]Metamorphoses I, 41.
[183]Republic III, viii.
[184]Cicero, Offices II, xvi.
[185]C. III, 82.
[186]B. II, 75.
[187]C.T. A. 46.
[188]Piers Plowman, B. X, 74.
[189]Pearl, 481.
[190]C.T. B. 1233.
[191]F. 1622.
[192]Emblems I, iv.
[193]St Patrick’s Day II, ii.
[194]Steele, Spectator, 493.
[195]Boswell, 16 September 1777.
[196]Sermon before the Queen, 24 February 1590.
[197]Probably under the influence of A.V. I Samuel XXV. 3-11.
[198]Leg. 1823.
[199]Hamlet II, ii, 619.
[200]As You Like It III, i, 14.
[201]Lear I, ii, 183.
[202]Errors I, ii, 19.
[203]Taming I, ii, 8-19.
[204]Hen. VI, Pt I, II, iv 81.
[205]In Timaeum CXXXVI.
[206]Gawain, 652.
[207]Hen. V, I, ii, 244.
[208]Othello I, iii, 37.
[209]Confessio VIII, 3023.
[210]Merchant IV, i, 39.
[211]Jonson, Alchemist I, i.
[212]Acts xxii. 29.
[213]Axiochus, 369.
[214]Cyropaedia I, ii, 3.
[215]982 b, Everyman ed., p. 55.
[216]1075 b.
[217]De Mundo, 392 a.
[218]Ethics, 1177 b.
[219]De Oratore III, xxxii.
[220]Ovid, Ex Ponto II, ix, 47.
[221]Journey to the Western Islands, Ostig.
[222]Boswell, 14 January 1766.
[223]History VI.
[224]Scope and Nature of University Education, IV.
[225]Catiline II, xii, 27.
[226]History I, 89.
[227]Metamorphoses VI, 118-20.
[228]Odes II, vii, 10.
[229]Odes III, xxiii, 5.
[230]Aeneid IV, 105.
[231]Epistles LXXV.
[232]Republic III, xxi.
[233]Epistles XCIX.
[234]Ad Familiares V, ii.
[235]Thomas Usk, Testament of Love III, ix.
[236]De Officiis XVI, 66.
[237]De Officiis III, iii, 13.
[238]Roman de la Rose, 19081.
[239]Troilus I, 393.
[240]Laws I, xxii, 58.
[241]Prologue, A. 306.
[242]Rambler, 79.
[243]Paradise Regained IV, 264.
[244]Elegy VII, 19.
[245]Ex Ponto I, ii, 32.
[246]Ad Familiares IV, ii, 10.
[247]Of Praise.
[248]To Atticus XV, 7.
[249]Othello V, ii, 288.
[250]History. Both in ch. X.
[251]Romans xiv. 5.
[252]Ibid. i. 28.
[253]Discourse on Method VI.
[254]Pt III, Sect. 4, Mem. 2, Subs. vi.
[255]Samson Agonistes, 1685.
[256]Fasti V, 484.
[257]Church-Porch, 431.
[258]Preface to The Rival Ladies, Essays, ed. W. P. Ker, vol. I, p. 7.
[259]Satires I, iii, 66.
[260]Aristotle, De Memoria, 450 a.
[261]Sonnet CXLI.
[262]See Pt I, Sec. 1, Mem. 2, Subs. vii.
[263]De Oratore I, iii, 12.
[264]F.Q. IV, x, 2.
[265]De Finibus IV, 19.
[266]Epistle 9.
[267]The Two Souls, 10.
[268]De Rege I, vi, 1598.
[269]De Natura Deorum III, 13.
[270]P.L. VI, 394.
[271]Farewell to Love, 18.
[272]Valediction Forbidding Mourning, 14.
[273]De Sensu, 436 a.
[274]C.T. l. 2262.
[275]Essay on Man I, 226.
[276]To Arbuthnot, 147.
[277]Essay I, iii, 4.
[278]Satire II, 80.
[279]L’Art Poétique, 181.
[280]Spectator, 2.
[281]Life of Prior.
[282]E.C. I, 23.
[283]Essay on Translated Verse, 115.
[284]Epistle 124.
[285]Locke, Essay II, i, 3.
[286]Rape of Lucrece, 1678.
[287]Metamorphoses XII, 166.
[288]Georgics I, 93.
[289]P.L. II, 278.
[290]Rambler, 200.
[291]Agonistes, 912.
[292]Sigismonda and Guiscardo, 270.
[293]Spectator, 231.
[294]On the Sublime etc., Introduction.
[295]Idler, 50.
[296]Sentimental Journey, ‘The Bourbonnais’.
[297]Mysteries of Udolpho, I, i.
[298]Hen. IV, Pt 2, I, ii, 191.
[299]See ibid. V, ii, 6-13.
[300]Merry Wives II, i, 148.
[301]Prologue to Aeneid.
[302]De Natura Deorum III, xiv.
[303]Discourse of English Poetrie, 1586. Ed. E. Arber (1895), P. 69.
[304]Essay II, ii, 1.
[305]Religio Medici II, 8.
[306]Montaigne II, xi.
[307]My translations are very free because Aristotle’s style is so telegraphic that fragments torn from their context and rendered at all literally would be hardly intelligible. I hope and believe I have not misrepresented his thought.
[308]Summa Theologiae I, 2ae, Q. VI, Art. 6.
[309]Ductor Dubit. I, v, Rule 8. Heber, vol. XII, p. 159.
[310]Twelfth Night I, iii, 124.
[311]Hist. I, xv.
[312]Matth. vi. 22.
[313]Met. V, xviii.
[314]Northanger Abbey, ch. XV.
[315]Othello I, iii, 247.
[316]III, 3. Heber, vol. XV, p. 508.
[317]Fourteen Sermons XXIII. Heber, vol. VI, p. 140.
[318]Sonnet LXVI.
[319]Carm. I, xxxviii.
[320]Ibid. I, vi.
[321]Spectator, 303.
[322]The Publisher to the Reader.
[323]Georgics III, 527.
[324]English version, l. 1014.
[325]Purgatorio XVI, 85.
[326]Hooker, V, lxxvii, 12.
[327]Midsummer Night’s Dream V, i, 82.
[328]P.L. XII, 364.
[329]Steele, Dedication of Tatler, vol. I.
[330]Eccles. x. 20.
[331]Saturnalia I, viii, 17.
[332]De Testimonio Animae V.
[333]Inst. VII, xxvii, 3.
[334]Gawain and the Green Knight, 1197.
[335]Timon II, ii, 184.
[336]L.G.W. 1254-5.
[337]C.T. A. 150.
[338]O.T. 330.
[339]Annals III, 30.
[340]Ibid. VI, 21.
[341]Metamorphoses XIII, 15.
[342]Leviathan I, vii, 31.
[343]Cooper’s Hill, 277.
[344]P.L. VI, 521.
[345]Sense and Sensibility, ch. XIV.
[346]Thesmophoriazusae, 477.
[347]I Cor. iv. 4.
[348]Epistles I, i, 61.
[349]Euripides, Orestes, 395-6.
[350]Fragment, 632.
[351]Marcus Aurelius VI, 30.
[352]Epistles, 97.
[353]Of Praise.
[354]Fragment, 669.
[355]P.L. VIII, 502-3.
[356]Arcadia V, ed. Feuillerat, p. 155.
[357]There is room for debate about the meaning of the word in a passage from Tacitus. ‘We have read that when Rusticus praised Thrasea, and Senecio praised Helvidius, it cost them their lives, and that the rage of government, not satisfied with the authors, extended to the books; three commissioners being appointed to have those monuments of high genius publicly burned. Our masters thought, it seems, that in that fire the voice of the Roman people, the liberty of the senate, and the conscientia of mankind, could be annihilated’ (Agricola II). It is tempting here to say ‘conscience’, and to give that word its full, later, sense. Einar Löfstedt almost seems to favour that interpretation when he speaks of Tacitus as ‘the man who first formulated this proud concept’ (Roman Literary Portraits, trans. P. M. Fraser, p. 153, Oxford, 1958). But surely—and this is probably what Löfstedt meant—conscientia contains ‘conscience’ only because it is conscientia in Lactantius’ sense; the communis sensus, the universal ‘feeling’ or ‘outlook’ of mankind? It might mean less. It might be the consciring of humanity to those truths the books contained. Of course consciring, as I have said, is normally the activity of a few. To make all men conscire would thus be a bitter and magnificent oxymoron; Domitian’s government had turned humanity itself into a sort of underground movement.
[358]C. A. Pierce, Conscience in the New Testament (1955).
[359]I Tim. i. 5.
[360]Ibid. 19.
[361]Acts xxiii. 1; cf. xxiv. 16.
[362]S.T. Ia, LXIX, art. 13.
[363]Pt I, Sec. 1, Mem. 2, Subs. 10.
[364]Ductor Dubitantium I, i, 1, para. 24. Works, ed. Heber, vol. XI, p. 382.
[365]Lydgate’s version, 4963-8.
[366]More, Dialogue of Comfort, I, xviii.
[367]Roper, Life of More.
[368]Spenser, F.Q. I, x, 23.
[369]Op. cit. p. 376.
[370]Homily, Rogation Week, Pt 3.
[371]Op. cit. pp. 369, 370, 376.
[372]P.L. III, 194-5.
[373]Tempest II, i, 278.
[374]See S. T. Bindoff, Tudor England, ch. VII.
[375]Sermons upon Human Nature III, 6.
[376]Cases of Conscience I, ii, 24.
[377]Sir Gibbie, ch. 37.
[378]Apud J. B. Black, Reign of Elizabeth (1936), p. 161.
[379]Hudibras I, iii, 1141-2.
[380]Taylor, op. cit. p. 410.
[381]Ibid. p. 411.
[382]Roper, Life of More.
[383]Diary, 7 February 1660-61.
[384]Op. cit. p. 410.
[385]P.L. X, 842-3.
[386]Op. cit. p. 371.
[387]Rambler, 110.
[388]Seventh Sermon before Edward VI.
[389]Op. cit. p. 390.
[390]M.W.W. I, i, 1.
[391]Pt 3, sec. 4, memb. 1, subs. 3.
[392]Taylor, op. cit. p. 366.
[393]Pt 3, sec. 4, memb. 1, subs. 4.
[394]Op. cit. p. 372.
[395]Merchant II, ii, 1.
[396]Othello III, iii, 204.
[397]Discourse upon Usury, ed. R. H. Tawney (1925), p. 234.
[398]Save and salve, and even solve, may replace one another rather oddly. Milton reproduces the Greek scientific canon sozein ta phainomena (to preserve, ‘get in’, do justice to, all the observed phenomena in any hypothesis you frame) correctly as ‘to save appearances’ (P.L. VIII, 82: cf. ‘to save the phenomenon’, Doctrine and Discipline I, i, Prose Wks. ed. Bohn, vol. III, p. 186). But Burton has ‘to salve all appearances’ (Pt 3, sec. 4, memb. 1, subs. 3) and even ‘to solve all appearances’ (Pt 2, sec. 2, memb. 3).
[399]Leviathan, Pt 2, XXII, ad fin.
[400]Essay, II, i, 11.
[401]Second Defence (1715).
[402]Even now this distinction can sometimes be made and can use the words consciousness and sentience; but only in learned works.
[403]Windsor Forest, 90.
[404]Task I, 156.
[405]Op. cit. ch. I.
[406]Prometheus Unbound II, v, 72.
[407]Elegy XIX, 13.
[408]Prelude VI, 134.
233

INDEX

A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z

A
ADDISON, wit, 105;
sense, 154;
sensibility, 159;
simple, 174
ÆLFRED, gecynde (adj.), 27;
gecynd (sbst.), 48;
freora, 114
ÆLFRIC, gecynde (sbst.), 26;
cynd (gender), 26
AGLIONBY, on conscience, 197-8
ALANUS AB INSULIS, 41 n., 44
ANDREWES, LAUNCELOT, villains, 118
APULEIUS, simplex, 171-7
AQUINAS, THOMAS, 61;
simpliciter, 168;
synteresis and conscientia, 194
ARISTOPHANES, xunoida, 187;
and au, 220
ARISTOTLE, phusis, 34, 39, 56;
history—tragedy, 57;
phusis, 65;
classification of his works, 68;
phusike, 70;
quoted, 110;
eleutheria, 126;
eleuthera by analogy, 127;
koine aisthesis, 147;
on sense and motion, 151;
haplôs, 167-8.
ARNOLD, 18, 230
ASCHAM, wits, 88
ASSEMBLY OF GODS, THE’, synderesis, 196
AUDEN, W. H., 94
AUGUSTINE, ST, 112;
communis sensus, 150
AULUS GELLIUS, senserint, 137
AUSTEN, JANE, sad, 83, 84;
sense—sensibility, 164;
conscious, 186
AUTHORISED VERSION, THE, freedom, 125;
single, 171;
harmless, 172;
lowly, 176;
thought, 182;
know by myself, 187
AXIOCHUS, eleutheriotaten, 126
B
BACON, sense, 142;
conscious, 139
BAXTER, physically, 70-1
BEDE, free, 114
BENSON, A. C., simple and simplicity, 179-80
BEOWULF’, gecynde (adj.), 27, 28;
sæd, 78;
gewitt, 87;
anfeald, 165
BERKELEY, furniture, 15;
conscious, 211
BERNARD, ST, conscience, 197
BERNARDUS SILVESTER, 41 n.
BERNERS, LORD, frank, 123-4
234
BLACK, J. B., 199 n.
BOETHIUS, 27;
natura, 48;
ingenium, 90
BOILEAU, esprit, 93-4;
bon sens, 154
BOSWELL, state of nature, 64;
nature, 64;
freedoms, 117
BRADLEY, F. H., simpler, 174
BROWNE, THOMAS, simpled, 166
BULLEYN, W. M., natural and nature, 30
BUNYAN, conscious, 189;
conscience, 206
BURNEY, FANNY, sententious, 141
BURTON, wit, 90, 100;
reprobate sense, 143;
common sense, 147;
simply, 169;
conscience, 194, 208, 209;
salve and solve, 210 n.
BUTLER, BP, conscience, 198
BUTLER (‘HUDIBRAS’), consciences, 199, 200
C
CAESAR, natura, 24
CARLETON BROWN, sadde, 82
CATULLUS, sentio, 137
CHALCIDIUS, liber, 123
CHAUCER, 23;
kinde (adj.), 29, 32;
nature, 40, 41;
naturelly, 44;
nature, 48;
sadde, 78;
sadly, 79, 80;
sad, 80, 81-2;
wittes, 88;
fredom, 115;
free, 116;
vileinye, 119-21;
sentence, 139-40;
sensualitee, 151;
simple, 177;
conscience, 183
CHESTERTON, 178
CHRONICLE, THE ANGLO-SAXON, sæd, 77
CICERO, natura, 25, 41;
naturâ—judicio, 60;
ingenium—ars, 91;
ingenium, 92;
liberi, 113;
liberales, 113;
sentiet, 134;
sensit, 136;
assensi and sentire, 137;
sententia, 138, 139, 140;
sensus, 142, 143;
communis sensus, 149;
sensus, 150;
simplex—concreta, 166
CLARKE, consciousness, 211
CLEANTHES, 41
CLEVELAND, 106, 108
COLERIDGE, natural, 52, 71
COLLINS, kind (adj.), 33
COTGRAVE, sad, 78
COURTESYANDCURTSY’, 99-100
COVERDALE, 77;
lowly and simple, 176
235
COWLEY, wit—judgment, 91;
his description of wit, 105, 106, 108
COWPER, 73;
sensibility, 160;
conscious, 213
CRANMER, 172
D
DANTE, natura, 39;
semplicetta, 177
DAVENANT, on wit, 101
DAVIES, wit, 87
DEFOE, conscience, 200
DEGUILEVILLE, Translunary—sublunary, 40 n.;
synderesis, 195
DENHAM, conscious, 185
DESCARTES, abonde en son sens, 143;
bon sens and sens, 153
DIGEST, THE, sensus, 145
DIOGENES LAERTIUS, suneidesis, 182
DONNE, 109, 110;
sentences, 141;
one sense, 150;
sense, 151-219
DRYDEN, 18;
kindness, 33;
nature—reason, 49;
wit and wits, 87;
wits, 90;
wit—poet, 96;
his definitions of wit, 101, 105;
his actual use of the word, 102;
momentary honesty, 107-8;
sense, 145;
sensible, 159;
simple, 175
DOUGLAS, sad, 79;
afaild, 165
DU BARTAS, 108
E
ELYOT, unnatural or supernatural, 65
EMPEDOCLES, phusis, 34, 35, 36, 37
EMPSON, W., 9, 93, 94, 96, 215
EPICTETUS, koinos nous, 146, 152
EURIPIDES, phuein, 34;
phusis, 34;
ephu, 46;
sunesis and sunoida, 188
F
FARQUHAR, sad, 83
FIELDING, sensible, 159
FLECKNOE, on wit, 101
FLETCHER, simples, 166
FLORIS AND BLANCHEFLOUR’, free, 115
FLOWER AND THE LEAF, THE’, unkindly, 65
FREUD, 20
236
G
GASCOIGNE, 108
GAWAIN AND THE GREEN KNIGHT’, kinde (adj.), 32;
franchise, 124;
simple, 175, 176;
conscience, 183
GAY, 83
GENESIS’, 40
GENESIS AND EXODUS’, kinde (sbst.), 27;
kinde (adj.), 31
GENEVA BIBLE, innocent, 172
GOLDING, ‘the supernaturalls’, 68
GOWER, sad, 78;
franchise, 125;
conscience, 183
GRIMSTONE, simple, 173
GROTIUS, 61
H
HAGGARD, H. RIDER, nature, 71
HALES, kind (adj.), 31-2
HALL, conscience, 199
HARROWING OF HELL’, YORK PLAY OF, free, 115
HEGELIANS, 106
HERACLITUS, 76
HERBERT, GEORGE, unkinde, 32;
nature, 54;
sense, 145, 152
HERODOTUS, phusis, 34
HOBBES, 61, 63;
conscious, 185, 211
HOLLAND, PHILEMON, freedom, 125
HOMILIES, BOOK OF’, conscience, 196
HORACE, 23;
natura, 25, 56;
ingeniis, 90;
sensi and sentiet, 135;
communis sensus, 147;
simplici, 174;
conscire, 187, 195
HOOKER, 61;
supernatural, 64;
physical, 71;
wit, 100, 149;
simply, 169;
simplicity, 179
I
IMITATION OF CHRIST, THE’, 54
ISIDORE, physici, 69
J
JOHNSON, naturally, 52;
nature, 55, 56;
state of nature, 63;
sad, 83;
wretches, 84;
poet, 95, 105;
definition of wit, 109;
generous and noble, 130;
sentences, 140;
sense, 154;
insensible, 158;
sensibility, 159;
simply, 169;
conscience, 206
JONSON, free, 125
JUVENAL, ingenuus, 113;
conscius, 189
237
K
KANT, 45
KNOX, MONSIGNOR, 174
L
LACTANTIUS, sensibile, 157;
conscientia, 182
LATIMER, sententiously, 141;
conscience, 206
LAXDALE SAGA, saddr, 77
LEAVIS, F. R. S., 94
LOCKE, common sense, 153;
sensible, 157;
conscious, 211, 212
LÖFSTEDT, EINAR, 191 n.
LUCAN, 94
LUCIAN, 94
LUCRETIUS, natura, 36;
gravis, 76;
ingenium, 89;
sentimus, 138;
sententia, 139
LYDGATE, sad, 79
LYLY, unkinde, 29
M
MACAULAY, LORD, liberal, 130;
sense, 143
MACAULAY, ROSE, 226
MACDONALD, conscience, 199
MACROBIUS, conscius, 182
MALORY, kynde (adj.), 28;
kindly, 28, 29;
natural, 32;
sadly, 79;
sad, 83;
simpler, 176;
simple, 176
MARCUS AURELIUS, phusis, 41;
eusuneidetos, 188
MARIANA, communis sensus, 150
MATTHEW, ST, haplous, 171
MENANDER, 112;
sunesis, 188;
sunesis theos, 192, 197
MILTON, critical, 20;
nature, 40, 47, 48;
grave, 76, 87;
sententious, 141;
sense reprobate, 144;
unexpressive, 157;
sensible and sensibly, 158;
plain (adj.), 174;
simple, 179;
conscious, 186;
conscience, 189, 197, 200, 205;
save appearances, 210 n.
MONTAIGNE, simple, 166
MORE, HENRY, conscience, 206-7
MORE, THOMAS, conscience, 196, 202-3
N
NEVILLE, LADY DOROTHY, 97
NEWMAN, liberal, 131
238
NORRIS, JOHN, simple, 174
O
ORIGEN, 97
OVERBURY, sentences, 140;
sense, 145
OVID, 40, 102, 106;
liberioris, 113;
ingenuas, 130;
sensit, 134;
sensus, 142, 144;
penetrabile, 157;
conscia, 185
OWL AND NIGHTINGALE, THE’, sade, 78
P
PARMENIDES, phusis, 35, 37
PAUL, ST, nous, 143;
sunoida, 187;
suneidesis, 192-3
PEARL’, kind (adj.), 32;
sad, 80
PEPYS, conscience, 204
PETER, ST, suneidesis, 192
PHAEDRUS, sentiat, 134;
sensus communis, 146
PHOENIX, THE’, gecynde (sbst.), 26
PIERCE, C. A., 192
PIERS PLOWMAN’, kynde (sbst.), 27;
unkynde, 30;
kinde (adj.), 32;
free, 115
PLATO, phusis, 34;
phusei—techne, 46;
creation of Man, 49;
phusei—nomô, phusis of justice, law of phusis, 60;
Politicus of, 217
PLOTINUS, phusis, 38
PLUTARCH, suneidos, 182
POPE, conscience—nature, 52;
nature, 55;
state of nature, 63;
nature’s self inspires, 71;
whose body nature is, 72;
wit, 87;
wit—art, 91;
wits, 93-4;
true wit, 106;
wit, 107, 108;
sense—thought and description—sense, 152;
good sense, 154;
conscious, 212
PRAYER BOOK, 27;
comfortable, 157;
conscience(s), 196;
conscience, 208
PSEUDO-CÆDMON, wit, 86
Q
QUARLES, free, 116
QUINTILIAN, natura, 46;
ingenium, 89;
ingenium—judicium, 91;
sententia, 139, 140;
sensus, 145;
sensus communis, 146
R
RACINE, 23
RADCLIFFE, MRS, sensibility, 160
RHEIMS VERSION OF N. T., sense, 144
239
RICHARDS, I. A., 215, 229
ROMAN DE LA ROSE’, nature, 41;
sadde, 78;
sad, 81;
villain, 118;
vilanie, 119;
frans, 123, 124;
sentence, 139;
simple, simples, 172, 176
RONSARD, 23
ROPER, conscience, 196
ROSCOMMON, sense, 156
ROSS, SIR DAVID, 34
RYMER, nature, 57-8
S
SANNAZARO, natura, 47
SCOTT, gentle—simple, 176
SENECA, natura, 47, 62;
ingenium, 89, 91;
sentiam and sentire, 136;
sensus (pl.), 149;
sensibile, 156;
conscientia, 188, 198
SEPTUAGINT, suneidesis, 182, 188
SHADWELL, poet, 95;
his description of wit, 101
SHAKESPEARE, physical, 4, 69;
natural, 28;
kind and natural, 30;
kindly, 32;
unnatural, 43;
nature, 50, 51, 54;
supernatural, 66;
physic, 69;
metaphysical, 70;
grave, 76;
sad, 82, 83;
wits, 88, 91;
wit and witty, 98;
liberal, 117;
villain, 121-3;
freedom, 125;
sentence, 140;
sense, 143;
wits and senses, 147;
common sense, 149;
sense and motion, 151;
sensible, 157, 158, 162, 163;
simple, 166;
simply, 170;
simple and simpleness, 172, 173, 179;
conscience, 183, 188, 204, 207-8, 209
SHELLEY, 217-18
SHERIDAN, free, 116
SIDNEY, natural, 28;
unkind—kind, 30;
common sense, 148, 189-190
SOPHOCLES, phunai, 34;
on divine laws, 59;
eleutheron, 112;
suneidos, 184;
suneidenai, 184;
sunoide, 189
SPENSER, 23;
heavy, 75;
frank, 124;
common sense, 149;
conscience, 196
STATIUS, 41
STEELE, free, 117;
simplicity, 179
STERNE, nature, 53;
grave, 76;
sensibility, 160
SWIFT, grave, 76;
simple, 174
T
TACITUS, ingenium, 89;
ingenia, 90;
sentire, 134, 136;
simplicissime, 171;
conscius and conscientia, 184;
conscientia, 191 n.
TASSO, natura, 39
240
TATIAN, suneidesis, 197
TAYLOR, JEREMY, 139;
simply, 169;
innocents, 173;
simple, 173;
conscience, 195, 197;
pretend, 200;
conscience, 206, 209
TENNYSON, sense—soul, 151
TERENCE, sententia, 138
TERTULLIAN, conscientia, 182
THACKERAY, 174
THOMPSON, nature, 72
TODD, 196
TYNDALE, innocent, 172
U
USK, sentence, 138
V
VARRO, divina natura, 73 n.
VERBICIDE, 7, 8, 131-2, 228
VILLEHARDOUIN, naturel, 28
VIRGIL, graviora, 75;
gravis, 76;
solidum, 79;
sensit, 135;
penetrabile, 157;
non repostae, 175
VULGATE, sensus, 143;
simplex, 171;
simplices, 172;
conscientia, 182
W
WEBBE, W. M., simple, 166
WHITGIFT, consciences, 199
WILDE, 139
WILSON, conscience, 210
WORDSWORTH, 56;
nature, 72;
sense, 142-219
WYCLIFFE, sad, 78
X
XENOPHON, eleutherous apo, 111;
eleuthera, 126

Transcriber’s Notes

[The end of Studies in Words by Clive Staples Lewis]